Friday, March 27, 2009

defalation

India Nears Deflation

Mar. 20 - Within a span of just seven months India has moved from a 16 year high inflation rate of 12.91 percent to a 32 year low inflation rate of 0.44 percent. The situation however represents a cruel paradox for consumers as food prices continue to rise during the deflation – food prices rose roughly nine percent year on year.

Deflation in India which is a result of the economic crisis and a subsequent cut in domestic demand, is threatening to lower growth in production and investments. Broking house CLSA has predicted that India’s GDP will grow by 4.6 percent in 2009-10, and that the domestic economy will stabilize only by early 2010. Further, it has projected public sector deficit to rise to 14 percent of GDP in 2009-10, and the rupee to fall to 57 to the dollar by the end of this year.

A negative inflation discourages investments in the economy. The real interest rate difference between nominal interest rate and inflation becomes very high, making funds costlier. As demand goes down, capacity utilization of manufacturing units declines. This discourages investment in capacity expansion, the Times of India said quoting a Citibank report "India Macroscope”.

The Indian government is doing all it can to spur consumption and investments. The RBI cut interest rates to 5 percent for the fifth time in the first week of March and the FIPB reduced restrictions on FDI cap. Nonetheless while domestic demand is low, exports continue to fall – exports fell to a 10 year low slumping 16 percent year on year.

Are we experiencing inflation or deflation?

When crude oil goes through the roof, Gold stagnates and economy in many countries are helpless, you may be wondering what is really happening – are we experiencing inflation or deflation?

The answer lies in a cause and effect syndrome. The world is really under some sort of slow deflation. US and other Western countries are experiencing a labor force restructuring. People who used to make six figures in Fortune 500 companies are losing their job and starting a small business or taking a huge pay cut to do something else. This deflation in turn is slowing the US and other Western economies and that is manifested by lower and lower bond yields worldwide for the last twenty years. The Corporations in US have difficulty in gaining pricing power. Hence they have to cut cost. That in turn is shipping jobs to India and China. That is creating more deflation in US and other Western economies.

Now in India and China though things are little different. Newly acquired imported jobs are providing a bonanza of cash in the hands of a few. These few in India and China can be millions because of general population size. Now these techies in India and factory workers in China are buying cars and other essentials to fulfill their American dreams.
As a result number of cars in India and China for example is quadrupling every year. Now guess why crude oil price is going up!

As Crude oil price is going up, this is further causing slowing down of US and other Western economies. That in turn is causing more deflation! And that is causing more export of jobs to India and China.

So what is this? This is the new global economy. Expansion and inflation in one part of the world and deflation on the other part.

So what will happen finally? That really depends upon which economies are in the driver seat. It is obvious that still the US economy is driving the whole world. If that is the case sooner or later, deflation in US will take over. For example, Microsoft may decide to ship a lot of jobs to India and save some money to fight deflation. Unless basic business model or cycle change, Microsoft will eventually go to their Indian counterpart and ask them to reduce cost of service. Walmart for example is already pressing the Chinese to cut cost to make them competitive in US. Bow India and China also start facing delation.

Like business cycles, this phenomenon may eventually reverse.

Monday, March 16, 2009

Global financial turmoil

The global financial turmoil and challenges for the Indian economy

* * *
It is my pleasure to be here this evening and to be able to share my thoughts with an exclusive gathering of bankers. Since this is an in-house meeting and we are professional colleagues, I propose to be frank and forthright. I am glad to know that the Bankers' Club in Kolkata has been recently revived and is engaged in promoting professional interaction within the banking community.
The global financial crisis is now the staple of front page news. Banks around the world, including those in India, are in the forefront of managing the challenge of crisis resolution. Since it is so topical, I would like to take this opportunity to share my perspective on the current global turmoil, its impact on India, the outlook for the Indian economy and the challenges that lie ahead for the Indian banking system, in particular.
Global financial outlook
The global financial situation continues to be uncertain and unsettled. What started off as a sub-prime crisis in the US housing mortgage sector has turned successively into a global banking crisis, global financial crisis and now a global economic crisis. Text book economics often cites housing as a prime example of a non-tradable good. It is paradoxical that a quintessentially non-tradable good as housing has triggered a crisis of global dimensions. This crisis is also the first of a kind in the sense that it is the first financial crisis since the Great Depression that originated in the advanced economies and rapidly engulfed the whole world. Such is the depth and sweep of financial globalisation. By far, the most frequently asked question (FAQ) today is whether the worst – in terms of the financial sector meltdown, and in particular, failure of financial institutions – is behind us. No one is really willing to take a definitive call on this, which is a sign of the increasing number of unknown unknowns.
Even as recently as six months ago, there was a view that the fallout of the crisis will remain confined to the financial sector and that, at the most, there would only be a shallow recession in the advanced economies. These expectations, as it now turns out, have been belied. The contagion has traversed from the financial to the real sector; and it now looks like the recession will be deeper and the recovery longer than earlier anticipated.
Global economic outlook
Many economists are now predicting that this “Great Recession” of 2008/09 will be the worst global recession since the 1930s. The IMF made its customary forecast for global growth in the World Economic Outlook published in October 2008. By early November, the IMF had revised its forecast for global growth downwards – from 3.9 per cent to 3.7 per cent for 2008, and from 3.0 per cent to 2.2 per cent for 2009. There are two inferences that follow from this. First, that the global situation has deteriorated rapidly, in a space of less than two months. Second, that 2009 is going to be a more challenging year than 2008.
Emerging economies
Ironically, even as late as six months ago, it was intellectually fashionable to subscribe to the “decoupling theory” – that even if advanced countries went into a downturn, emerging
BIS Review 162/2008 1
economies will, at worst, be affected only marginally, and will largely steam ahead on their own. In a rapidly globalising world, the decoupling theory was never very persuasive; given the evidence of the last few months – capital flow reversals, sharp widening of spreads between sovereign and corporate debt, and abrupt currency depreciations – the decoupling theory has almost completely lost credibility. Growth prospects of emerging economies have most definitively been undermined by the ongoing crisis with, of course, considerable variations across countries.
Impact of the crisis on India
India too is having to weather the negative impact of the crisis. As the impact on India unfolds, there are two frequently asked questions: First, how is that India is affected when it came out of the Asian crisis relatively unscathed? Second, why is India affected even when its exports account for only 15 per cent of its GDP? The answer to both the questions lies in globalisation. We are certainly more integrated into the world economy today than ten years ago at the time of the Asian crisis. Integration into the world implies more than just exports. Going by the common measure of globalisation, India's two-way trade (merchandise exports plus imports), as a proportion of GDP, grew from 21.2 per cent in 1997-98, the year of the Asian crisis, to 34.7 per cent in 2007-08. If we take an expanded measure of globalisation, that is, the ratio of total external transactions (gross current account flows plus gross capital flows) to GDP, this ratio has increased from 46.8 per cent in 1997-98 to 117.4 per cent in 2007-08. These numbers are clear evidence of India's increasing integration into the world economy over the last 10 years.
We must also note another important difference between the crisis in the advanced countries and the developments in India. While in the advanced countries the contagion spread from the financial to the real sector, in India, the slowdown in the real sector is affecting the financial sector, which in turn, has a second-order impact on the real sector.
The Indian banking system
The Indian banking system is not directly exposed to the sub-prime mortgage assets. It has very limited indirect exposure to the US mortgage market, or to the failed institutions or stressed assets. Indian banks, both in the public sector and in the private sector, are financially sound, well capitalised and well regulated. The average capital to risk-weighted assets ratio (CRAR) for the Indian banking system, as at end-March 2008, was 12.6 per cent, as against the regulatory minimum of nine per cent and the Basel norm of eight per cent. Even so, India is experiencing the knock-on effects of the global crisis, through the monetary, financial and real channels – all of which are coming on top of the already expected cyclical moderation in growth. Our financial markets – equity market, money market, forex market and credit market – have all come under pressure mainly because of what we have begun to call “the substitution effect” of: (i) drying up of overseas financing for Indian banks and Indian corporates; (ii) constraints in raising funds in a bearish domestic capital market; and (iii) decline in the internal accruals of the corporates. All these factors added to the pressure on the domestic credit market.
Simultaneously, the reversal of capital flows, caused by the global de-leveraging process, has put pressure on our forex market. The sharp fluctuation in the overnight money market rates in October 2008 and the depreciation of the rupee reflected the combined impact of the global credit crunch and the de-leveraging process underway.
Outlook for India
The outlook for India, going forward, is mixed. There is evidence of a slow down in the economic activity. The real GDP growth has moderated in the first half of 2008-09. Industrial
2 BIS Review 162/2008
activity, particularly in the manufacturing and infrastructure sectors, is decelerating. The services sector too, which has been our prime growth engine for the last five years, is slowing, mainly in the construction, transport and communication, trade, hotels and restaurants sub-sectors. For the first time in seven years, exports have declined in absolute terms in October 2008. Recent data indicate that the demand for bank credit is slackening despite comfortable liquidity in the system. Higher input costs and dampened demand have dented corporate margins while the uncertainty surrounding the crisis has affected business confidence.
Inflation
On the positive side, headline inflation, as measured by the wholesale price index, has fallen sharply, and the decline has been sustained for the past four weeks, pointing to a faster-than-expected reduction in inflation. Largely, the falling commodity prices have been the key drivers behind the disinflation; however, some contribution has also come from slowing domestic demand. The reduction in prices of petrol and diesel announced last week, and a cut in the excise duties should further ease the inflationary pressures. To be sure, consumer price inflation for the months of September and October 2008 did increase. This is possibly owing to the firm trend in food-articles inflation and the higher weight of food articles in the measures of consumer price inflation. Historically, there has been a positive correlation between wholesale and consumer price inflation, and given this correlation, consumer price inflation too can be expected to soften in the months ahead.
RBI's policy stance
The Reserve Bank's monetary policy stance has consistently been to balance growth, inflation and financial stability concerns. When inflation surged earlier this year, the RBI had moved quickly to tighten policy. Then again, reflecting the unfolding global situation and expectation of decline in inflation, RBI has adjusted its monetary stance over the last couple of months. The endeavour of our monetary stance has been to manage liquidity – both domestic and forex liquidity – and to ensure that credit continues to flow for productive activities.
Measures taken so far
The RBI has taken several measures aimed at infusing rupee as well as foreign exchange liquidity and to maintain credit flow to productive sectors of the economy. Measures aimed at expanding the rupee liquidity included significant reduction in the cash reserve ratio (CRR), reduction of the statutory liquidity ratio (SLR), opening a special repo window under the liquidity adjustment facility (LAF) for banks for on-lending to the non-banking financial companies (NBFCs), housing finance companies (HFCs) and mutual funds (MFs), and extending a special refinance facility, which banks can access without any collateral. The Reserve Bank is also unwinding the Market Stabilisation Scheme (MSS) securities, roughly synchronised with the government borrowing programme, in order to manage liquidity.
Measures aimed at managing forex liquidity include upward adjustment of the interest rate ceilings on the foreign currency non-resident (banks) [FCNR(B)] and non-resident (external) rupee account [NR(E)RA] deposits, substantially relaxing the external commercial borrowings (ECB) regime, allowing the NBFCs and HFCs access to foreign borrowing and allowing corporates to buy back foreign currency convertible bonds (FCCBs) to take advantage of the discount in the prevailing depressed global markets. The Reserve Bank has also instituted a rupee-dollar swap facility for banks with overseas branches to give them comfort in managing their short-term funding requirements.
BIS Review 162/2008 3
Measures to encourage flow of credit to sectors which are coming under pressure include extending the period of pre-shipment and post-shipment credit for exports, expanding the refinance facility for exports, counter-cyclical adjustment of provisioning norms for all types of standard assets (except in case of direct advances to agriculture and small and medium enterprises which continue to be at 0.25 per cent) and risk weights on banks' exposure to certain sectors which had been increased earlier counter-cyclically, and expanding the lendable resources available to the Small Industries Development Bank of India (SIDBI), the National Housing Bank (NHB) and the Export-Import Bank of India (EXIM Bank).
To improve the flow of credit to productive sectors at viable costs so as to sustain the growth momentum, the Reserve Bank signalled a lowering of the interest rate structure by reducing its key policy rate viz., the repo rate by 250 basis points from 9.0 per cent as on October 19 to 6.5 per cent by December 8, 2008.
Although, we remain vulnerable to global financial and economic developments, the measures taken so far have eased the liquidity and credit flow situations considerably. I must also add that in managing the impact of the global crisis, we have been mindful that no policy initiative is totally costless. Managing this delicate balance between costs and benefits has been one of our challenges.
The measures taken by the RBI have been appreciated and criticised. I would like to assure you that we give as much importance to our critics as our admirers. While some of the criticism has been fair and value adding, some of it stems from an inadequate appreciation of the RBI perspective. I thought it may be useful to give our perspective so as to inform public debate on important monetary policy issues.
Everyone is now agreed that the way forward on this crisis at the present time is too uncertain. Even today, it is not possible to clearly see the path of the crisis and its resolution over the coming months. It is just not possible to have a precise road map all laid out to be unleashed in one go. This crisis does not allow us that luxury. And, mind you, India is not unique in this respect. Almost every country, whether or not directly affected, is having to manage under uncertainty. There are simply too many unknown unknowns.
In the circumstances, the stance of the RBI has been to respond to the evolving situation swiftly and effectively, and to the extent possible, in anticipation of immediate developments. We do have a road map that is comprehensive and practical. It would be our endeavour to adapt this road map to the evolving global developments and implement it flexibly and pragmatically. Our approach, as indeed of every prudent central banker around the world, has been to "cross the river by feeling the stones". The RBI will continue to be on vigil and do everything possible within its mandate to mitigate the impact of the crisis on the Indian economy.
The challenges ahead
Let me now turn to the major challenges facing the banking system in the country, particularly in the wake of the global financial crisis.
The first challenge: maintaining the credit flow
The outlook, both for the world and for India, continues to remain uncertain. The future trajectory of the global crisis is not yet clear. As I mentioned earlier, the year 2009-10 will be more challenging than the current one. There was a noticeable decline in the credit demand in the month of November 2008 but it is not yet clear if it was a one off episode or it reflects a trend. If it is indicative of slowing economic activity, it would be a major challenge for the banks to ensure healthy flow of credit to the productive sectors of the economy. As you know, economic growth, even in normal times, requires efficient financial intermediation. An economic downturn, therefore, requires even more efficient financial intermediation – and 4 BIS Review 162/2008
this is a major challenge that the banking community has to address. There is a need to ensure a steady credit flow to the real sector of the economy in order to sustain demand even while maintaining credit quality.
There are two aspects to lending viz., availability and cost of credit. While the availability of credit should not be an issue, the cost of credit seems to be an issue at the current juncture. There seem to be two reasons inhibiting the banks from extending credit: first, a high weighted-average cost of funds because of high interest rates on deposits; and second, concerns about credit quality, which makes the banks risk averse, particularly in lending to certain segments. During the last one month, there has been a sharp reversal in trend and, as noted earlier, credit demand seems to be slackening. The reduced funding demand on the banks should enable them to reduce the interest rates on deposit and thereby reduce the overall cost of funds. In addition, from a macro perspective the decelation of headline inflation noticed so far and the expectations of softening of inflation in the months ahead should enable a reduction in nominal interest rates. These developments in turn, would facilitate lending at lower interest rates, making fresh lending more viable and, at least partly obviating the risk aversion of the banks.
Let me assure you that the RBI, on its part, will continue to maintain adequate liquidity in the system to enable the flow of credit to the economy.
The second challenge: how do we reform financial sector regulation?
By far, the most contentious and most voluble debate triggered by the crisis has been about the flaws in the regulatory architecture of the financial sector. Several issues have come to the fore. I will mention just a few. How can complex derivative products, which transmitted risks across the system, be made more transparent? What are the financial stability implications of structured products like credit derivatives? Are exchange traded derivatives better than over-the-counter (OTC) derivatives? How do we eliminate the drawbacks of the “originate-to-distribute” model? Is universal banking, the model that the United States has now turned to, appropriate? Can we apply the same regulatory regime for both wholesale and retail banks?
The burden of all the above questions is to identify the drawbacks in the present regulatory regimes and indicate possible solutions. There is no doubt that we must pursue all these questions. In doing so, I would urge that we remember two things. The first thing to remember is that no one size fits all. For example, universal banking may be good in some of the countries and in some of the situations, and not so in others. The second thing to remember is that some regulations, arguably, have been behind the curve. There is no denying that regulations have to keep pace with innovations in the financial markets but in doing so, we must be mindful of the risks of over-tightening the regulations lest they stifle innovation.
The third challenge: regulatory forbearance and relaxing regulatory norms
There has been a sustained demand from various quarters for exercising regulatory forbearance in regard to extant prudential regulations applicable to the banking sector. As a part of counter-cyclical package, we have already made several changes to the current prudential norms. These include: (a) reduction in the risk weights for claims on unrated corporates and commercial real estate to 100 per cent; (b) reduction in the provisioning requirement for all standard assets to 0.40 per cent; (c) permitting housing loans to be restructured even if the revised payment period exceeds ten years; (d) making the restructured commercial real estate exposures eligible for special treatment if restructured before June 30, 2009.
There are demands for further regulatory forbearance. For example, there has been a demand to relax the asset classification norms by increasing the period of delinquency
BIS Review 162/2008 5
beyond the current norm of 90 days after which the loan asset is required to be classified as non-performing. The objective underlying the demand is to permit the banks to avoid recognising non-performing loans (NPLs) for a longer period. Is it desirable to change the NPL norm by relaxing the 90 day rule? The demand is presumably premised on the argument that the relaxation in the norm will make the banks' financials look better, allow them to reserve less, conserve capital, and may even allow them to offer more credit (or at least not cut back on credit). However, there are several forceful arguments against the relaxation sought. Let me mention a few.
(i) Delay in recognition of NPL removes pressure on the banks to deal promptly with the problem. History suggests that delayed recognition of impairment in the value of the assets makes the problems only worse. The sooner banks restructure the loan (through, say, CDR mechanism) or, where appropriate, send the loan for collection, the better.
(ii) This global downturn is likely to be a prolonged one. If banks do not recognise their problem loans here and now, and deal with them expeditiously, the problem will only get compounded with the passage of time and will keep haunting them in future.
(iii) The prudential regulatory norms ought not to be changed lightly, especially when markets are on edge. If the impression gains ground that the modified norms under-state the extent of impairment and over-state the asset quality in the banking sector, the markets could suspect the worst and needlessly penalise the banks through market discipline.
These are the issues we need to reflect on in moving towards further regulatory forbearance.
The fourth challenge: effective implementation of Basel II framework
As you are aware, a part of the Indian banking system has already migrated to the Basel II Framework effective March 31, 2008 and the remaining commercial banks are slated to do so by March 31, 2009. However, having regard to the state of preparedness of the system, we have, for the present, adopted only the simpler approaches available under the Framework. The RBI is yet to announced the timeframe for adoption of the Advanced Approaches in the Indian banking system but the migration to these Approaches is the eventual goal – for which the banking system will need to start its preparations in all earnestness.
The migration to the Advanced Approaches poses several significant challenges to the bankers and, as the banking regulator and supervisor, also to the RBI. The first challenge is the availability of long time-series data for computing the risk parameters required under the Advanced Approaches. Good-quality, consistent and reliable data and information relating to the loan portfolios of the banks as also sophisticated IT resources are critical to the proper risk assessment under the Basel II framework. Data limitation is a key impediment to the design and implementation of credit risk models. This may prove to be a major challenge for us in India, given the wide-spread branch network – though the increasing computerisation in the banking industry should prove to be of great help.
The second challenge is that the Advanced Approaches for credit risk and operational risk envisaged under the Basel II Framework also require use of risk models by the banks. This, in turn, requires internal validation of these models by the banks themselves as also by the supervisors before the models can be permitted to be used for regulatory capital purposes. Such a validation process demands expert skills which need to be developed and nurtured.
Third, since Basel II Framework is primarily about ensuring robust risk management in the banks, its effective implementation, particularly the Advanced Approaches, will demand rapid and significant upgradation of skills – both at the level of the banking system as also within the RBI. In this context, the challenge that banks are likely to face will be multi-faceted, viz., assessing skill requirements, identifying and bridging the gaps, identifying talents, putting the
6 BIS Review 162/2008
available talents to optimum use, attracting fresh talents, retention of talents, and change management. Banks would, therefore, need to pay special attention to strengthening their risk management infrastructure, in all its dimensions, including the human resources. We, in the RBI, are mindful of our part of the challenges in this regard and are taking necessary measures.
The implementation of Basel II requires closer cooperation, information sharing and co-ordination of policies among sectoral supervisors, specially in the context of financial conglomerates. The existence of separate supervisory authorities to regulate different segments of the markets within a jurisdiction may create challenges in implementation of Basel II not only within a jurisdiction but also across jurisdictions – which would require effective cross-border supervisory cooperation and co-ordination.
The fifth challenge: the challenge of banking development and financial inclusion in Eastern India
Banking development in the eastern region of the country, as measured by several parameters, is lagging behind the national average. Let me give some evidence to illustrate this.
• In March 2008, the all-India per branch population coverage was 15,400. For the eastern region, the figure varied from 25,000 in Bihar to 9,600 in Sikkim..
• In March 2007, at the all-India level, the per capita deposit was Rs. 28,600. The corresponding figure for the eastern region was Rs. 14,400. Similarly, as against the per capita credit of Rs 28,600 at the all-India level, the corresponding figure for the eastern region is only Rs. 7,200.
• In March 2007, at the all-India level, the population of people having bank accounts was 41 per cent. The corresponding population for the eastern region was only 30.7 per cent, ranging from 21.1 per cent for Bihar to 39.6 per cent for West Bengal.
• In March 2007, at the all-India level, the credit-deposit ratio was 74.5 per cent. For the eastern region, the ratio was just 50 per cent.
In terms of infrastructure coverage and other development indicators, the eastern region is not as developed as other regions of the country. Admittedly, this affects the credit absorption capacity and may also explain some of the lagging parameters mentioned above. However, this can not be an excuse for inaction. It should be impetus for vigorous action.
Finance can lead development just as much as it can be led by it. This is specially true for the poor. Nearly a third of the people of Bihar and West Bengal are below the poverty line. Through greater financial inclusion it should be possible to provide savings, loan and insurance products at affordable prices and this can generate income and employment in a very significant measure.
We must recognise that the opportunity cost of formal finance for the borrower is so high that mere financial inclusion can unlock value that today is accruing to rentiers and informal finance providers. This apart, transaction costs can be reduced through the kind of scale of operations that only banks are capable of achieving and this itself become a source of value creation.
Financial inclusion can not be reduced to a mere number game. The actual impact of financial inclusion and expanded banking coverage must be felt at the grass-root level. I find that a number of measures have been initiated to deepen the banking penetration in the region. For example, in West Bengal, a Task Force for extending banking facilities in unbanked Gram Panchayats (GP) was constituted by the State Level Bankers’ Committee in December 2007. The task force has identified 511 GPs at which bank branches will be opened in next three years and at 427 GP-centres in the following three years. I understand
BIS Review 162/2008 7
that the State Government has agreed to provide premises adjacent to the GP offices and extend other facilities like road connection and power at such centres.
Where a full fledged branch can not be opened immediately, banks could look at covering the unbanked areas through satellite offices, weekly branches, or use the business correspondent model for ensuring greater coverage within a shorter period. Information Technology (IT) solutions should also be explored for providing a back bone of credit information, customer information apart from facilitating more efficient credit delivery and reducing cost of payments and remittances.
I understand there has been an interesting and innovative experiment undertaken in West Bengal for promoting financial inclusion. A Financial Inclusion/Literacy Campaign was launched in an urban slum area viz., the Basanti Colony, Ultadanga, Kolkata in mid-October 2008 in association with six commercial banks. These banks are the State Bank of India, United Bank of India, UCO Bank, Allahabad Bank, Bank of India and Bank of Baroda – which had branches in the vicinity of the slum area. All six banks were allotted separate counters for opening of accounts as well as to campaign for their bank-specific products. Free photo facility for account holders was provided and the cost was shared by all the participating banks. The initiatives such as this should be pursued and the full range of financial services provided to these areas. I understand that the Local Council extended support for obtaining identity documents required for opening of bank accounts. This experiment demonstrates what banks can do if only they are responsive, sensitive, proactive and result oriented.
Coming to sectoral flow of credit, while the share of agriculture in the State’s SDP is higher than at the all-India level, the share of agricultural credit in total credit is roughly the same for the State. This points to the need to look at bankable schemes in the agriculture sector. Also, NABARD has a very significant role to play in this region. As the micro and small enterprises account for 7.2 per cent of total credit in the region, SIDBI too, as a development finance institution, has to play a prominent role in accelerating and catalysing the flow of bank credit to the MSE sector in the region.
Although not often acknowledged, effective financial intermediation has been one of the important factors behind India’s recent growth episode. Efficient financial intermediation is a formidable challenge where poverty and disadvantage are high. You, as senior bank managers in the eastern region of the country, have a bigger challenge and greater opportunity. A bigger challenge because you have to be even more efficient than elsewhere, and a greater opportunity because by being responsive and sensitive, you can make "a bigger difference".
Conclusion
Going forward, developments in the real economy, financial markets and global commodity prices point to a period of moderation in growth with declining inflation. What is heartening though is that the fundamentals of our economy continue to be strong. Once calm and confidence are restored in the global markets, economic activity in India will recover sharply. But a period of painful adjustment is inevitable. It is our collective challenge – for you, the bankers, and for us at the RBI – to respond to this extraordinary situation effectively and return India to its path of growth and poverty reduction.
Thank you.

Friday, March 13, 2009

Das capital

Capital, Volume I

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Jump to: navigation, search
Part of a series on
Marxist theory
Karl Marx
Communism portal

Capital, Volume I is the first of three volumes in Karl Marx's monumental work, Das Kapital, and the only volume to be published during his lifetime. Originally published in 1867, Marx's aim in Capital, Volume I is to uncover and explain the laws specific to the capitalist mode of production and of the class struggles rooted in these capitalist social relations of production.

Contents

[hide]

[edit] Part One: Commodities and Money

Chapters 1-3 begin with a dense theoretical discussion of the commodity, value, exchange, and the genesis of money. As Marx writes, "Beginnings are always difficult in all sciences ... the section that contains the analysis of commodities, will therefore present the greatest difficulty."[1]

[edit] Chapter 1: The Commodity

Section 1. The Two Factors Of The Commodity: Use-Value And Value (Substance Of Value, Magnitude Of Value)

Marx begins his analysis with what he calls the “commodity.” Marx explains that the commodity is something independent of ourselves that meets a human want or need of any kind. It is clear that Marx is not concerned with why people buy commodities, only that people buying commodities is inevitable. Marx explains that the commodity has something called a “use-value.” The use-value is determined by how useful the commodity is. The actual use-value however is intangible. He explains that use-value can only be determined “in use or consumption.” After determining the use-value of the commodity, something called an “exchange-value” is then derived from it once the commodity is exchanged. He explains this as the quantity of other commodities that it will exchange for. He gives the example of corn and iron. No matter their relationship, there will always be an equation where a certain amount of corn will exchange for a certain amount of iron. He sets up this example to say that all commodities are in essence parallel in that they can always be exchanged for certain quantities of other commodities. He also explains that one cannot determine the exchange value of the commodity simply by looking at it or examining it. The exchange-value is not material. In order to determine the exchange-value, one must see the commodity being exchanged with other commodities. Marx explains that these two aspects of commodities are at the same time separate but also connected in that one cannot be discussed without the other. Marx explains that while the use-value of something can only change in quality, the exchange-value can only change in quantity.

Marx then goes on to explain that the exchange-value of a commodity is merely a portrayal of its value. Value is what makes all commodities connected in that they can all be exchanged with each other. The value of a commodity is determined by its Socially necessary labor time. Socially necessary labor time is defined by “the labor time required to produce any use-value under the conditions of production normal for a given society and with the average degree of skill and intensity of labor prevalent in that society.” Therefore, Marx explains that the value of a commodity does not stay constant as advances or variations in labor productivity occur for any number of reasons. However, value does not mean anything unless it conjoins back to use value. If a commodity is produced that no one wants or has use for, “the labor does not count as labor”, and therefore it has no value. He also says that one can produce use-value without being a commodity. If one produces a commodity solely for his own benefit or need, he has produced use-value but no commodity. Value can only be derived when it the commodity has use-value for others. Marx calls this social use-value. He says all of this to explain that all aspects of the commodity (use-value, exchange-value, and value) are all separate from each other, but are also essentially all connected to each other.

[edit] Section 2. The Dual Character Of The Labour Embodied In Commodities

Marx discusses the relationship between labor and value. Marx states if there is a change in the quantity of labor expended to produce an article, the value of the article will change. This is, in fact, a direct correlation. Marx gives an example of the value of linen versus cloth to explain the worth of each commodity in a capitalist society. Linen is hypothetically twice as valuable as thread because more socially necessary labor time was used to create it. Use-value of every commodity is produced by useful labor. Use-value measures the actual usefulness of a commodity, whereas value is a measurement of exchange value. The source of value is labor-power. Objectively speaking, linen and thread have some value. Different forms of labor create different kinds of use-values. The value of the different use-values created by different types of labor can be compared because both are expenditures of human labor. One coat and ten yards of linen take the same amount of socially necessary labor time to make, so they have the same value.

[edit] Section 3. The Value-Form or Exchange-Value

[edit] (a) The Simple, Isolated, or Accidental Form of Value

In this chapter Marx explains that commodities come in double form. Commodities come in natural form and value form. We don't know commodities' value until we know how much human labor was put in it. Commodities are traded between each other, after their value is decided socially. Then there is value-relation, which lets us trade between different kind of commodities. Marx explains value without using money. Marx uses 20 yards of linen and a coat to show the value of each other. (20 yards of linen = 1 coat, or: 20 yards of linen are worth 1 coat) pg. 139. Marx calls this an equivalent form. He adds that the value 20 yards of linen is just 20 yards of linen, there is no expression of value. Linen is an object of utility and that we cannot tell its value until we compare it to another commodity. Figuring out the value of commodity depends on its position in the expression value. Also commodities value depends in its being expressed or a commodity which the value is being expressed.

[edit] (b) The Total or Expanded Form of Value

Marx begins this section with an equation for the expanded form of value: "z commodity A = u commodity B or = v commodity C or = w commodity D or = x commodity E or = etc." where the lower case letters (z, u,v, w, and x) represent quantities of a commodity and upper case letters (A, B,C,D, and E) represent specific commodities so that an example of this could be: "20 yards of linen = 1 coat or = 10 lb. tea or = 40 lb. coffee or = 1 quarter of corn or = 2 ounces of gold or = ½ ton of iron or = etc."[2] Marx explains that with this example of the expanded form of value the linen “is now expressed in terms of innumerable other members of the world of commodities. Every other commodity now becomes a mirror of linen’s value.”[2] At this point, the particular use-value of linen becomes unimportant, but rather it is the magnitude of value (determined by socially necessary labor time) possessed in a quantity of linen which determines its exchange with other commodities. This chain of particular kinds (different commodites) of values is endless in that it contains every commodity and is constantly changing as new commodities come into being.

[edit] (c) The General Form of Value

Marx Begins this section with the table:

    \begin{bmatrix}         1 & \mbox{Coat}\\         10 & \mbox{lb. of tea}\\         40 & \mbox{lb. of coffee}\\         1 & \mbox{Quarter of Corn}\\         2 & \mbox{Ounces of Gold}\\         1/2 & \mbox{Ton of Iron}\\         x & \mbox{Commodity A etc.}\\     \end{bmatrix} = 20 \mbox{ yards of linen} [3]

Then he divides this sub-set of section 3 three parts.

(1) The changed character of the form of value.
After highlighting the previous two sub-sets Marx goes on to describe how now that there is a unified exchange-value for said commodities the only thing that differentiates them now is their individual use-value. “The general form of value, on the other hand, can only arise as the joint contribution of the whole of commodities.” (159) Making these values socially influenced and requiring qualitative equivalency as use-values.
(2) The development of the relative and equivalent forms of value: their independence.

Here Marx talks about the inter-relatedness of the relative form and the equivalent form. He first explains that there is a correlation between them even though they are polar opposites. He states that we must also realize that the equivalent form is a representation and an off shoot of the relative form.

“This equivalent has no relative form of value in common with other commodities; its value is rather, expressed relatively in the infinite series of all other physical commodities.” (161)

Things cannot be either completely relative or equivalent. There must be a combination to express the magnitude and universal equivalency. That form is the expanded relative form of value, which is a

“specific relative form of value of the equivalent commodity” (161)

(3) The transition from the general form of value to the money form.
This is the transitory idea between taking the General Form (the universal equivalent form for all general commodities) and turning it into the Money Form. Here Marx describes how there can be a commodity that is so universal to all commodities that it actually that it excludes itself to the point of no longer being an equivalent commodity but a representation of a commodity. The idea of its socially accepted commodity exchange value is so universal that it can be then transition into a form of money. IE Gold.

[edit] (d) The Money Form
    \begin{bmatrix}         1 & \mbox{Coat}\\         10 & \mbox{lb. of tea}\\         40 & \mbox{lb. of coffee}\\         1 & \mbox{Quarter of Corn}\\         20 & \mbox{Yards of linen}\\         1/2 & \mbox{Ton of Iron}\\         x & \mbox{Commodity A etc.}\\     \end{bmatrix} = 2 \mbox{ ounces of gold} [4]

Here Marx illustrated the shift to “Money Form." Universal equivalent form or universal exchangeability has caused gold to take the place of linen in the socially accepted customs of exchange. Once it had reached a set value in the world of commodities gold became the money commodity. Which is distinct from Section A, B, or C.

Now that gold has a relative value against a commodity such as linen is can now attain price form.

“The ‘price form’ of linen is therefore: 20 yards of linen = 2 ounces of gold, or, if 2 ounces of gold when coined are £2, 20 yards of linen = £2.” (163)

This illustrates the application of price form as a universal equivalent. The simplified application of this idea is then illustrated as:

x of commodity A = y of commodity B

[edit] Section 4. The Fetishism of the Commodity and Its Secret

Marx's inquiry in this section focuses on the nature of the commodity, apart from its basic use-value. In other words, why does the commodity in its value-form (exchange) appear to be something other than the aggregation of homogenous human labor? Marx contends that due to the historical circumstances of capitalist society, the values of commodities are usually studied by political economists in their most advanced form: money. These economists see the value of the commodity as something metaphysically autonomous from the social labor that is the actual determinant of value. Marx calls this fetishism - the process whereby the society that originally generated an idea eventually, through the distance of time, forgets that the idea is actually a social and therefore all-too-human product. What this means is that this society will not look beneath the veneer of the idea (in this case the value of commodities) as it currently exists. They will simply take the idea as a natural and/or God-given inevitability that they are powerless to alter. Marx compares this fetishism to the manufacturing of religious belief; people initially create a deity to fulfill whatever desire or need they have in present circumstances, but then these products of the human brain appear as autonomous figures endowed with a life of their own, which enter into a relation both with each other and with the human race (165). Similarly, commodities only enter into relation with each other through exchange, which is a purely social phenomenon. Before that, they are simply useful items, but not commodities. Value itself cannot come from use-value because there is no way to compare or contrast the usefulness of an item; there are simply too many potential functions. So once in exchange, their value is determined by the amount of socially useful labor-time put into them because labor can be generalized. It takes longer to mine diamonds than it does to dig for quartz, thus diamonds are worth more. Fetishism within capitalism occurs once labor has been socially divided and centrally coordinated, and the worker no longer owns the means of production. They no longer have access to the knowledge of how much labor went into a product because they no longer control its distribution. From there, the only obvious determinant of value to the mass of people is the value that has been assigned in the past. Thus the value of a commodity seems to arise from a mystical property inherent to it, rather than from the labor-time, the actual determinant of value.

[edit] Chapter 2: The Process of Exchange

In Chapter 2 Marx explains commodity exchange and the fact that commodities need assistance to be exchanged. Marx states that "humans are made for each other to be holders or representatives of commodities."[5] The commodities need to be exchanged so we must look to the owners of the object and view them as owners of private property. In order for an object to enter as a commodity the guardian must place the object in relation to all other objects. For the owner, the object has no direct use-value but having a use-value for everyone else. The only use-value for the owner is within its own exchange-value. So the owner will decide to sell his item in return for objects with use-values for himself. If the items change hands this is an exchange, and it gives each of the items a value related to each other. So far exchange is an individual process and the owner looks at every other commodity as an equivalent to his own, making his commodity the universal equivalent. Since all owners look at the situation like this there is no actual universal equivalent and the objects are not yet commodities but still only use-values. So a universal equivalent must be realized. Only society can make this happen through setting aside a particular commodity to be the universal equivalent, making this item money. “Money necessarily crystallizes out of the process of exchange, in which different products of labour are in fact equated with each other, and thus converted into commodities.”[6] As the process of exchange furthers on objects begin to get produced solely for exchange and a distinction between a use-value and an exchange-value is created. Before an individual commodity was set aside as money, any exchange of commodity showed a simple form of value showing, x commodity A= y commodity B. Once a commodity is set aside it takes on the money form of value, putting all commodities against it. A form of money usually comes from two places, from the most important article exchanged within a community or an object showing wealth within a society, like cattle in some cultures. Gold and silver were acquired as a natural form of money because their natural properties showed good qualities of a form of money. Though also commodities, gold and silver have a uniform quality and can divided into different increments allowing the metals to naturally be used as money. Making these commodities into money gives the metal its value-form and not its value. Even though a commodity is set aside as money we must still figure what a certain amount of the commodity is worth. This is done by looking at the labor time it took to produce and equating it to the labor time of another commodity. The exchange of commodities went from individual trades of commodities to a complex system of money and value. Closing the chapter, Marx states that "Men are henceforth related to each other in their social process of production in a purely atomistic way. ... because the products of men's labour universally take on the form of commodities."[7]

[edit] Chapter 3: Money, or the Circulation of Commodities

[edit] 1. The Measure of Values

Functions of Metallic Money

In chapter 3 section I Marx examines the functions of money commodities. According to Marx the main function of money is to provide commodities with the medium for the expression of their values, i.e. labor time. The function of money as a measure of value serves only in an imaginary or ideal capacity. That is, the money that performs the functions of a measure of value is only imaginary because it is society that has given the money its value. The value that is contained in one ton of iron for example, is expressed by an imaginary quantity of the money commodity, which contains the same amount of labor as the gold.

Multiple Forms of Metallic Money

As a measure of value and a standard of price money performs two functions. First it is the measure of value as the social incarnation of human labor and secondly it serves as a standard of price as a quantity of metal with a fixed weight. As in any case where quantities of the same denomination are to be measured the stability of the measurement is of the utmost importance. Hence the less the unit of measurement is subject to variations the better it fulfills its role. Metallic currency may only serve as a measure of value because it is itself a product of human labor.

Commodities with definite prices appear in this form: a commodity A= x gold; b commodity B= y gold; c commodity C= z gold, etc where a, b,c represent definite quantities of the commodities A, B,C and x, y,z definite quantities of gold. In spite of the varieties of commodities their values become magnitudes of the same denomination, gold-magnitudes. Since these commodities are all magnitudes of gold they are comparable and interchangeable.

Price

Price is the money-name of the labor objectified in a commodity. Like the relative form of value in general, price expresses the value of a commodity by asserting that a given quantity of the equivalent is directly interchangeable. The price form implies both the exchangeability of commodities for money and the necessity of exchange. Gold serves as an ideal measure of value only because it has already established itself as the money commodity in the process of exchange.

[edit] 2. The Means of Circulation

[edit] (a) The Metamorphosis of Commodities

In this section Marx further examines the paradoxical nature of the exchange of commodities. The contradictions that exist within the process of exchange provide the structure for “social metabolism”. The process of social metabolism “transfers commodities from hands in which they are non-use-values to hands in which they are use-values…” (198). Commodities can only exist as “values” for a seller and “use-values” for a buyer. In order for a commodity to be both a “value” and a “use-value” it must be produced for exchange. The process of exchange alienates the ordinary commodity when its antithesis, the “money commodity” becomes involved. During exchange, the money commodity confronts the ordinary commodity disguising the true form of the ordinary commodity. Commodities and money are at opposites spectrums, and exist as separate entities. In the process of exchange, gold or money, functions as “exchange-value” while commodities function as “use-values”. A commodity’s existence is only validated through the form of money and money is only validated through the form of a commodity. This dualistic phenomenon involving money and commodities is directly related to Marx’s concept of “use-value” and “value”.

Commodity-Money-Commodity
C − > M − > C

Marx examines the two metamorphoses of the commodity through sale and purchase. In this process, “as far as concerns its material content, the movement is C-C, the exchange of one commodity for another, the metabolic interaction of social labor, in whose result the process itself becomes extinguished” (200).

C −  > M

First metamorphosis of the commodity, or sale. In the process of sale, the value of a commodity, which is measured by socially necessary labor-time, is then measured by the universal equivalent, gold.

M −  > C

The second or concluding metamorphosis of the commodity: purchase. Through the process of purchase all commodities lose their form by the universal alienator, money. “Since every commodity disappears when it becomes money it is impossible to tell from the money itself how it got into the hands of its possessor, or what article has been changed into it” (205).

M −  > C = C −  > M

A purchase represents a sale although they are two separate transformations. This process allows for the movement of commodities and the circulation of money.

[edit] (b) The Circulation of Money

The circulation of money is first initiated by the transformation of a commodity into money. The commodity is taken from its natural state and transformed into its monetary state. When this happens the commodity “falls out of circulation into consumption”. The previous commodity now in its monetary form replaces a new and different commodity continuing the circulation of money. In this process, money is the means for the movement and circulation of commodities. Money assumes the measure of value of a commodity (i.e.) the socially necessary labor-time. The repetition of this process constantly removes commodities from their starting places, taking them out of the sphere of circulation. Money circulates in the sphere and fluctuates with the sum of all the commodities that co-exist within the sphere. The price of commodities varies by three factors. “…the movement of prices, the quantity of commodities in circulation, and the velocity of circulation of money” (218).

[edit] (c) Coin. The Symbol of Value

Money takes the shape of a coin because of how it behaves in the sphere of circulation. Gold became the universal equivalent by the measurement of its weight in relation to commodities. This process was a job that belonged to the state. The problem with gold is that it wore down as it circulated from hand to hand. The introduction of paper money as a representation of gold arose from the state as a new circulating medium. This form of imaginary expression continues to mystify and intrigue. Marx views money as a “symbolic existence” which haunts the sphere of circulation and arbitrarily measures the product of labor.

[edit] 3. Money

[edit] (a) Hoarding

The exchange of money is a continuous flow of sales and purchase. Marx goes on to say, “In order to be able to buy without selling, he must have previously sold without buying.” This simple illustration demonstrates the essence of hoarding. In order to potentially buy, without selling a commodity in your possession, you must have hoarded some degree of money in the past. Money becomes greatly desired due to potential purchasing power. If you have money, you can exchange this for commodities and vice versa. However, while satisfying this newly arisen fetish for gold, the hoard causes the hoarder to make personal sacrifices.

[edit] (b) Means of Payment

In this section Marx analyzes the relationship between debtor and creditor and exemplifies the idea of the transfer of debt. In relation to this, Marx discusses how the money-form has become a means of incremental payment for a service or purchase. He states that the “function of money as means of payment begins to spread out beyond the sphere of circulation of commodities. It becomes the universal material of contracts.” Due to fixed payments and the like, debtors are forced to hoard money in preparation for these dates. “While hoarding, as a distinct mode of acquiring riches, vanishes with the progress of civil society, the formation of reserves of the means of payment grows with that progress.”

[edit] (c) World Money

Countries have reserves of gold and silver for two purposes: (1) Home Circulation; and (2) External Circulation in World Markets. Marx says that it is essential for countries to hoard, as it is needed “as the medium of the home circulation and home payments, and in part out of its function of money of the world.” With all of this discussed hoarding and the aforementioned idea of hoarded money’s inability to contribute to the growth of a capitalist society, Marx states that banks are the relief to this problem. “Countries in which the bourgeois form of production is developed to a certain extent, limit the hoards concentrated in the strong rooms of the banks to the minimum required for the proper performance of their peculiar functions. Whenever these hoards are strikingly above their average level, it is, with some exceptions, an indication of stagnation in the circulation of commodities, of an interruption in the even flow of their metamorphoses.”

[edit] Part Two: The Transformation of Money into Capital

Chapters 4-6 connect the abstract discussion of commodities, money, and value begun in Part I with their role in the formation of class relations under capitalism.

[edit] Chapter 4: The General Formula For Capital

In this chapter, Marx explains what capital is and how it is produced. The form of capital is money, yet not all money is capital. In Marx’s words there is “money as money" and "money as capital" (247). For money to be converted into the form of capital, it must undergo a deliberate process based on the circulation of commodities in an exchange market.

There are two different forms of commodity circulation: the direct or simple form of circulation (C-M-C) and the capital-generating form (M-C-M). Two common elements can easily be identified: the sale of a commodity (C-M) and the purchase of a commodity (M-C). Clearly the two contrast simply by their order in which the sale and purchase occur.

In the first form (C-M-C), a commodity is produced in order that one may acquire the means to purchase another commodity i.e. “selling in order to buy” (247). This particular form of commodity circulation is essentially a closed system. Once a commodity has been obtained by the purchase (M-C), the commodity exits the exchange-market thereby achieving its aim as a use-value, consumed according to necessity. The money is simply expended achieving its objective as a medium of exchange between two qualitatively different commodities.

The second, capital-generating form of commodity production (M-C-M) is simply an inversion of the previous form. In this instance, money purchases a commodity (M-C) in order that it be sold for money i.e. "buying in order to sell" (248). In contrast to the simple form of circulation, the capital-generating form culminates in the reflux, or return of money back to the capitalist as the desired result. Essentially money is exchanged for money (M-M). Since money is the starting point and conclusion of the capital-generating form of circulation "its determining purpose, is therefore exchange-value" (250). Consequently, use-values of commodities become negligible while the exchange-value of a commodity acquires meaning solely in the context of exchange. Therefore, in order for money to retain its form as capital it must remain in circulation otherwise it would simply be expended.

Finally, we must consider the role and motivations of the capitalist in the capital-generating form of circulation. If one expends money for the sake of receiving its return, then the capitalist necessarily desires its augmentation known as surplus-value. Since capital must remain in circulation, it manifests itself as ongoing process without end. The new value (original + surplus) becomes the starting point of a new cycle for the capitalist to exchange his money for more money. Therefore, the general formula for capital becomes M-C-M' in which M'=M+ΔM or the original value of money plus some increment of money, or surplus-value.

[edit] Chapter 5: Contradictions in the General Formula

After distinguishing money as capital (M-C-M) from money in general, Marx raises the question of how the capitalist accrues surplus-value by buying a commodity and then selling it. The key problem is how the exchange of equivalent values can produce more value. He rejects 5 possibilities:

  • First: Marx recognizes that use-value changes among buyers. So, one could just sell the commodity to the buyer with the most use-value and charge more to them. However, use-value does not determine value which is what is being created as a surplus. Since money is the universal equivalent of value, “the circulation of commodities involves a change only in the form of their values”.[8] As above, one can exchange 2oz of gold for only 1 coat and get only 2oz of gold for that coat, so long as the socially necessary labor time remains constant. Use-value plays no role in these formulas.
  • Second: In principle, “commodities may be sold at prices which diverge from their values, but this divergence appears as an infringement of the laws governing the exchange of commodities”.[9] Yet, the capitalist may possess some privilege by which s/he can sell above value. However, other capitalists have this privilege and overcharge the first capitalist who then loses his/her profit. The result is nominal price inflation which only changes the purchasing power of money, but not the real value.[10]
  • Third: There could be a class of people who consume but do not produce. They pay for commodities, and thus have money, without having produced and sold some commodity beforehand. The “free” money they thus put into circulation can be used to artificially alter exchange-values. However, since the consumption class has money without producing anything, the money must come from those outside of the consumption class. (Marx gives the example of Roman taxes.) Thus this class uses others' money to buy those people's products. No actual surplus-value is being created.[11]
  • Fourth: It may be that the capitalist overcharges a buyer as in the second rejection, but the buyer cannot recover the lost value and the capitalist will not be overcharged him/herself. However, there is still no surplus-value. If the buyer has $40 and the capitalist a $10 shirt, there is a total value of $50 in circulation. If the buyer pays $20 for the $10 shirt and has $20 left over, there is still a total value of $50. The only change is distribution of wealth.[12]
  • Fifth: Since the circulation of commodities is between equivalent values, any surplus-value must emerge outside of this circulation. However, outside of circulation, the value of a commodity is only the labor put into it. The producer “cannot create values which can valorize themselves.” Surplus-value thus cannot emerge outside of circulation.[13]

Conclusion: “Circulation, or the exchange of commodities, creates no value”.[14] Only labor does. And, since nothing external to circulation creates value, something must be operating within circulation which is not circulation itself. Marx closes with the contradiction: "The transformation of money into capital has to be developed on the basis of the immanent laws of the exchange of commodities, in such a way that the starting-point is the exchange of equivalents".[15]

[edit] Chapter 6: The Sale and Purchase of Labour-Power

Marx Starts off this chapter by stating that the change in the value of money into capital can’t happen in the second act of circulation, but takes place in the first act, M-C. This change can only originate from the use-value of the commodity, which comes from its consumption. The money-owner must find a commodity with a use-value that is also a source-value. This such commodity is labour power.

Labour power is the mental and physical capabilities of a human being, which are set in motion whenever a person produces a use-value. Labour power can only be found on the market when a free worker is available. This worker must be free in two ways. First he must be free as a worker; he must be willingly disposing of his labour power as his own commodity. But the worker must make sure that he sells his labour power for only a limited period of time otherwise he will become a commodity himself, a slave. Second he must have no other commodity for sale; he is free of them all. In order for one to sell commodities other than his own he must have means of production, or raw materials, and a free worker does not usually have these, he usually only has his own labour to sell.

The division between men who are owners of money or commodities and men who only have their labour to sell is not a natural process. It is clearly the production of a past historical development, the product of many economic revolutions. It is a process of the capitalist mode of production. The historical condition of capital’s existence is not just because of the circulation of money and commodities. It is present because a free worker puts himself out there, willingly, for an owner of means of subsistence and production to scoop up and take advantage of.

How is labour power’s value determined? The value of labour power is determined by the labour power necessary for the production and reproduction of it. Labour power exists as the capacity of the living individual, what it takes for the individual to maintain himself. For his maintenance he requires some form of means of subsistence. Means of subsistence is what keeps the worker going, he must consume before and while he produces. The value of labour power is the value of the means of subsistence the owner of the labour power requires. An individual’s natural needs vary with the social conditions he is used to in his country.

The sum of a worker’s means of subsistence is complicated. It must also include the means necessary for the worker’s replacements. This is necessary to capital because capital requires an undiminished supply of labour. Education and training for the worker must be included in the cost as well. Some means of subsistence are used every day, such as food and water, and must be replaced every day. While others, such as clothing, need to be replaced after longer intervals. These commodities must all be available to the worker through his average income in order for him to be able to produce labour power.

A consequence of labour power as a commodity is that it doesn’t immediately pass into the hands of the buyer. Its value is already determined before it enters circulation, but its use-value is only determined later. The money of the buyer serves as means of payment. In every country with the capitalist form of production the money-owner doesn’t pay for labour power until it is exercised for a set period of time. So the worker is advancing the use-value of his labour to the money-owner.

At the end of this chapter Marx states that we must leave the sphere of circulation or commodity exchange in order to see how capital produces and how it itself is produced. When we leave this sphere a certain change takes place. “He who was previously the money-owner now strides out in front as a capitalist; the possessor of labour power follows as his worker.”

[edit] Part Three: The Production of Absolute-Surplus Value

In chapters 7-11, Marx elaborates his analysis of exploitation and the extraction of surplus-value. He highlights both the fundamental way in which capital seeks to increase the rate of surplus-value through lengthening the working day, as well as the variety of ways workers strive to resist this increased exploitation.

[edit] Chapter 7: The Labour Process and the Valorization Process

[edit] 1. The Labor Process

The utilization of a worker’s labor-power is the labor process. The process changes the objects being worked upon—which was the intention of the worker at the start of the process—and creates use-values which can be called products or commodities. Labor will ultimately be objectified in the final product produced by this process. Marx points out that this production of use-values (the labor process) is the same under capitalism or any other economic system, and that the simple elements of this process are: 1. Purposeful activity—the work itself
2. An object on which work is carried out (object of labor)
a. Marx calls the object of labor a raw material when it has undergone some alteration by means of a previous labor process.
3. Instruments of labor
a. A thing or complex of things which the worker uses in acting on the object of labor
b. Marx considers all objective conditions necessary for carrying out the labor process to be instruments of labor.

The means of production are made up of the instruments and object(s) of labor. These instruments and objects are often the use-values of previous labor. A hammer (instrument) used to nail up sheetrock (object) and the sheetrock itself are both use-values (products of earlier labor) incorporated into the labor process of building a wall as well as means of producing a wall. If a use-value involved in the labor process is an object of labor, instrument of labor or product of labor depends on that use-values’ role in the process. The fact that use-values produced by prior labor can become means of production for other labor illustrates that labor itself is in part a process of consumption. Marx calls this consumption productive consumption. The persons consuming in the course of action of productive consumption are the workers whose labor-power is the force that gives the labor process its life.

Capitalism and the labor process:
To the capitalist labor-power is a necessary use-value or product purchased to animate the labor process. Without labor-power, the capitalist cannot be successful—his/her objects and instruments of labor would be wasted raw materials with no one to create the use-value or commodity the capitalist wishes to sale on the market. Marx points out that labor-power is a commodity which the capitalist consumes by causing the worker (who is selling the labor-power) to consume the means of production by his/her labor. Marx points out two phenomena of the capitalist’s consumption of labor-power: 1. The worker works under the control of the capitalist to whom his labor belongs.
2. The product is the property of the capitalist and not that of the worker—the person who made the product.

[edit] 2. The Valorization Process

The capitalist strives to produce a use-value with exchange-value (a commodity) that has a greater value than the sum of its parts (the means of production and labor-power). The process of production must therefore be understood as the synthesis of the labor process and the process of creating value.

Marx uses as an example of valorization the spinning of cotton into yarn. When the capitalist purchases 10 lb. of cotton at its full value of 10 shillings, the price conveys the labor objectified in the cotton. In addition, all of the socially necessary means of production used up in the cotton’s production, which Marx represents in the wear and tear of the spindle, have a value of 2 shillings.

To determine the value of the yarn, then, all of the successive processes necessary to produce the cotton, manufacture the spindle, and spin the yarn must be taken into account. The values of the means of production, the 12 shillings, are a part of the total value of the product.

There are two conditions that must be met for this process to produce value. First, a use-value must have been produced. Second, the labor-time used to produce the use-value (in this case yarn) must be no more than that which is socially-necessary.

Yet these factors still only amount to a portion of the total value of the yarn; labor constitutes the remainder. Since labor-power is “absorbed” by the raw material in the form of spinning, the resulting yarn “is now nothing more than a measure of the labor absorbed by the cotton.”[16]

Value is added to the yarn by the labor objectified in it. The value of a day’s labor-power (six hours of labor) is 3 shillings. Assuming the spinner can turn 10 lb. of cotton into 10 lb. of yarn in six hours, the cotton contains six hours of labor, the same amount contained by 3 shillings of gold. Spinning, then, has added a value of 3 shillings to the cotton.

The total value of the 10 lb. of yarn is calculated by adding all of the socially necessary means of production used up and all of the socially necessary labor absorbed. Two days of labor were absorbed by the cotton and spindle, a half a day by the process of spinning. The two and a half days of labor are represented by a piece of gold valued at 15 shillings. This is thus the price of the 10 lb. of yarn.

In this process, though, the capitalist has not created surplus-value, even though value has been added to the product (10 shillings to produce the cotton, 2 shillings for the worn spindle, and 3 shillings to purchase the labor-power). The capitalist has broken even, which is not why they entered business.

The capitalist realizes that the worker spins for only six hours to survive for twenty-four hours, and could remain effective for twelve hours. This increases the value created twofold. The two and a half days of labor become five, the 10 lb. of yarn becomes 20, and the value created becomes 30 shillings. The price of the 20 lb. of cotton is thus 30 shillings, but the total value of the labor and means of production is only 27 shillings. A surplus-value of three shillings has been created, and money has been transformed into capital.

Everything is exchanged equally and the capitalist pays the full value for each commodity consumed.

[edit] Chapter 8: Constant Capital and Variable Capital

In Chapter 8, Marx describes how labor simultaneously transfers the previous use-value of the all the means of production and creates surplus value within a product. The differences in these types of values create the division between Constant Capital and Variable Capital. Marx defines Constant Capital as, “That part of capital, therefore, which is turned into means of production, i.e. the raw material, the auxiliary material and the instruments of labor, does not undergo any quantitative alteration of value in the process of production. [17]Constant Capital remains a constant quantifiable entity because the means of production that transfer use-value to raw materials, “never transfer more value to the product than they themselves lose during the labor process by the destruction of their own use value." [18]Even with a change in price, in Marx’s example, the raw material of cotton, the new price of that cotton will transferred to the product, but no new value has been created.

Marx contrasts Constant Capital with Variable Capital saying, “That part of capital which is turned into labor-power does undergo an alteration of value in the process of production. It both reproduces the equivalent of its own value and produces an excess, a surplus value, which may itself vary, and be more or less according to circumstances” [19]. With Variable Capital, the laborer not only transfers the value of all previous inputs, but also adds surplus value to the product. Marx provides the example; while it may only take 6 hours of socially necessary labor time to incorporate into the product the equivalent for the value of labor power, the process lasts longer, say 12 hours. The activity of labor power then not only reproduces its own value, but also produces a surplus value which is the difference between the value of the product and the elements consumed in the formation of the product, i.e. the means of production and the labor power. Even if improved technology in the labor process allows one worker to do one hundred times the work of ten men, this only serves to increase the Constant Capital while decreasing Variable Capital in the labor process and does not affect the essential difference between the two [20].

[edit] Chapter 9: The Rate of Surplus Value

1. The Degree of Exploitation of Labor-Power Capital advanced is the sum of constant capital and variable capital.

C = c + v

For example $500 (advanced capital) = $410 (constant) + $90 (labor)

Through the process of production a surplus, s, is created. The resulting sum is C’ constituting the total of constant capital, variable capital, and surplus value. Thus

C’ = (c + v) + s

For example $590 = $410 + $90 + $90 (surplus)

Surplus value comprises the excess of the value of the commodity produced over the capital advanced for production. Constant capital transfers only part of its value during the process of production, as the remainder of its value continues to reside in the machinery. This does not alter the calculation because the constant value incorporated in the equation is only concerned with the materials actually utilized in production. For example, if the constant capital equals $410, it could be broken down as such

$ 312 raw materials
$ 44 auxiliary materials
$ 54 value of the machine worn away during production

c = $ 410

Let’s say the total value of the machinery itself costs $1054. The only value imparted to the product is the $54 of wear, because the machinery retains $1000 of value. If this value is entered into the equation, it must be entered on both sides.

C = $500, + $1000 = $1500 C’ = $590, + $1000 = $1590

Either considering or neglecting the value retained by the machinery results in the same difference, or surplus value, of $90. Constant capital, c, will therefore refer solely to the value actually consumed during production. The constant capital advanced transfers all of its value to the product and therefore cannot produce surplus value. Thus we can equate constant capital with 0. The new value produced is therefore not the total value of the product, (c + v) + s or $590, but the sum of variable capital and surplus value, v + s or $180. The absolute quantity of surplus value is $90. The relative quantity of surplus value, or rate of exploitation, can be determined by s/v. In our example this equates to 90/90, or % 100.

2. The Representation of the Components of the Value of the Product by Corresponding Proportional Parts of the Product Itself

In order to explain the conversion of money into capital, Marx offers an example of yarn production. A 12-hour workday produces 20 lbs of yarn valued at a total of 30s. 24s of value are the result of constant capital (20 lbs of cotton at 20s, and 4s for repair of the machine). The remaining 6s includes the variable capital (the worker’s wage) and the surplus value (profit). The workers wage is 3s and 3s of surplus are produced, equaling a % 100 rate of exploitation (3s/3s). This exploitation occurs not only during the process of spinning the yarn, but during the production of all its constituents (i.e. picking the cotton, building the spindle etc.)

3. Senior’s “Last Hour”

In section 3 of chapter 9, Marx condemns the economic analysis of cotton mills conducted by Professor Nassau W. Senior in his pamphlet “Letters on the Factory Act, as it affects the cotton manufacture.” The pamphlet suggest that the entirety of the surplus value is produced during the last hour of a 12 hour workday, with the remainder contributing to the wage of the worker. Marx disputes Senior’s analysis on the grounds that Senior failed to separate constant and variable capital, instead including the mill and machinery as one factor and the wages and raw material as a second factor. This failure to discern between variable and constant capital was considered by Marx to be a crucial blunder. Marx also notes that the value produced during each hour is likely to be equal, and if 11 hours were contributing to wages, with 1 hour producing net profit, that proportion should be reflected in the ratio of wages paid to profits.

Senior’s calculations do not take into account the value embedded in the constant capital and takes for granted their contribution of value to the finished product, instead of acknowledging that the method of transferring that value is through the use of labor-power.

4. Surplus Produce

Surplus-produce refers to the portion of the product that represents surplus-value. Like the ratio of surplus value to variable capital, the relative quantity of surplus production is determined by the ratio of surplus-produce to the part of the total product in which necessary labor time is incorporated. The sum of necessary and surplus labor constitutes the working day.

[edit] Chapter 10: The Working Day

"1. The Limits of the Working Day."

Value of labor power is the necessary labor time required for a worker to produce an amount equal to his means of subsistence. Any amount of time worked beyond the necessary labor time is called surplus labor. The Working Day = A-------B----------C. The line AC represents the working day. AB is the necessary labor time and BC is surplus labor. Under the Capitalist system, Marx says that a working day can never be reduced to necessary labor time only. This would not profit the capitalist and profits are the capitalist’s goal. Furthermore, employees are only a personification of capital and capital’s only aim is, “the drive to valorize itself.” Marx proceeds to describe the two factors that limit the maximum length of the working day. First, there are physical limits to labor power. A worker can only work for so long before he must rest, eat, sleep, etc. In addition to physical limitations, there are moral obstacles that limit the working day. “The worker needs time in which to satisfy his intellectual and social requirements, and the extent and the number of these requirements is conditioned by the general level of civilization.” The capitalist seeks to create the most surplus value he can by extending the working day to absorb the greatest possible amount of surplus labor, i.e. extending line segment B --- C as far as possible. In other words, the capitalist is like any other buyer of commodities; he wants to extract the maximum use value of his commodity, which in this case is labor power. The consumption of labor power creates more value than it costs, and labor power is a very unique commodity in that it is the only valorizing commodity. All other commodities are congealed quantities of labor power lying dormant when not in the process of production. Marx says, “Capital is dead labor which, vampire-like, lives only by sucking living labor, and lives the more, the more labor it sucks.” This is the logic at the heart of the capitalist’s desire to increase the length of the working day. Now, the worker who sells this commodity, labor power, hopes to be able to reproduce that same commodity and have it ready to resell again the next day. If the working day is extended too far, the capitalist may extract a greater quantity of labor power than the worker is able to restore before his next shift begins. This will cause significant deterioration in the health of the worker. Marx goes on to describe how the process of overwork leads to the worker being unfairly compensated for the exchange value of his labor power reflected in his daily wages. He provides the following example: If the average length of time a worker can live and do a reasonable amount of work is 30 years, the value of his labor power for which he is paid from day to day is: 1 /( 365 x 30) or 1 / 10,950 of its total value. If worked too hard and the value of his labor power is consumed in 10 years, he is still paid the same amount. That is 1 / 10,950 of his labor power daily instead of 1 / 3650; therefore, he is only paid 1 / 3 the value of his labor power daily, and is robbed of 2 / 3. A normal length working day is being demanded by the worker as the seller of his commodity in a market governed by the law of commodity exchange. If the capitalist consumes a quantity of labor power that takes three days time to replenish, but has only paid for one day’s worth of labor power, then the worker as the seller of his commodity is being cheated. Hence the worker simply seeks equal value for the sale of his commodity, and the capitalist seeks, equally justified, the right to consume the labor power he has purchased as efficiently as possible. The two parties are both merited and yet at ends with one another, therefore, a struggle between collective capital (class of capitalists) and collective labor (working classes) over the length of the working day ensues.

"2. The Voracious Appetite for Surplus Labor. Manufacturer and Boyar."

“Capital did not invent surplus labor”, begins Marx. But in capital, necessary labor time and surplus labor time are meshed together, indistinguishable to the worker, creating an opaque understanding of who the worker is working for when. Historically, the time spent by the worker working for himself compared to the time the worker spent working for his feudal lord, or other type figure head, was easily distinguishable because there were separate fields that the worker would work, one for his own food production, and then another field belonging to the feudal lord would receive so many allotted days of labor. In capital factory systems, the proportion of work spent toward the workers own reproduction of his means of subsistence, the necessary labor time, and that designated to producing surplus value for the capitalist is unknown to the worker, enabling the capitalist to exploit that relation leaving the worker still unaware of the magnitudes of this proportion as it is hidden behind the value of the worker’s daily wage. Marx then focuses of the tendency of the owners of the means of production to further exploit and continue the extraction of greater and greater amounts of surplus labor out of workers, often by unscrupulous means. He gives two main examples. The first is the system of the “corvée” in the Danubian provinces of precapitalist Russia. The second example is that of a fraudulent capitalist factory owner. Under the corvée system of the early 19th century, the peasant owed a specific quantity of labor to the landlord annually. This labor consisted of 12 general labor days, one day of field labor, and one day of wood carrying. This amounted to a total of 14 days a year. These days were not average work days, however. They amounted to the total time necessary to produce an average daily product. Russian leaders took such great liberties in deciding what an average daily product was so that it turned out to be equal to three days of actual work to produce. The 14 days of corvée thus became 42 days of required labor time. This same process eventually repeated once 42 days had become the expected but unspoken standard quantity of product; the amount of work to produce this newly expected quantity then amounted to 126 days. Now, after subtracting the Sundays of the year and the days of rainy season, the 14 days of corvée, as one Moldavian boyar put it, “drunk with victory, ‘amount to 365 days in the year.” Marx then gives a few more examples of ways in which the landlords were able to extract more and more surplus value from the exploited working class. He refers to gold miners and cotton pickers (when cotton was in high demand) being worked to literal death because there labor yielded such large quantities of surplus value that the labor power as a commodity was expendable. The second main example for the strong appetite capitalists have for surplus labor is that of a fraudulent factory owner that illegally extends the length of the working day. He does this by starting work 10 or 15 minutes early or by shaving a few minutes off of the beginning and ending of breaks and lunch hours. These robberies of minutes here and there add up to hours of uncompensated surplus labor over the course of a week, and weeks of surplus labor over the course of a year, all from a few moments the capitalist tries to steal. The gains are significant because, “moments are the element of profit.” Even when demand for an industry is low, the capitalist still aims to exploit the worker all the more. They call running less days of production, short time labor, or hiring part time employees, and when such circumstances are in effect, the capitalist tries all the harder to increase surplus labor time to obtain profits while he can off the exploitation of workers that will not be permanent employees. In 1850 the Factory Act had been implemented to limit the hours of the working day to just10 hours, but all of these examples of fraudulent management still occur. The reason being that, “The profit to be gained by it’ (over-working in violation of the Act) ‘appears to be, to many, a greater temptation than they can resist; they calculate upon the chance of not being found out; and when they see the small amount of penalty and costs, which those who have been convicted have had to pay, they find that if they should be detected there will still be a considerable balance of gain…”

"3. Branches of English Industry without Legal Limits to Exploitation"

In this section, Marx presents the historical debate regarding the work day and the exploitation of children. Using examples of match manufacturing, bread-making, lace manufacture, pottery, wall paper making, milliners, train engineers, and blacksmiths, Marx describes the issues children, women and men faced by working extremely long hours in poor conditions at very young ages. In many cases, these children died or faced long-term ailments related to pulmonary infections or general malnutrition and physical degradation because of particulate matter in the production process and extremely rigorous hours. Marx also covers similar issues of exploitation of entire populations as sighted by doctors over time. Working at this rate, skipping meals and through all hours of the night, day after day was destroying the working class. Reservation for meal times and being able to eat away from the dirty conditions of the machinery operating areas is becoming a value that will be necessary to mandate for workers rights as highlighted by all of these injustices Marx found documented. Food must be supplied to the laborer in the same sense that machines need oil, a steam engine needs coal and water: workers, the instruments of labor need food.

"4. Day-Work and Night-Work. The Shift-System"

Means of production (constant capital) exists to be used to produce commodities. When not in use, no valorization of surplus-labor is occurring. In order to produce 24 hours a day, the capitalist realized that by instituting shift-work, he could both maximize his profits while allowing the individual worker to get his necessary rest. Yet, even with the shift system, we see that the capitalist still aims to exploit the worker by obtaining more surplus labor time from the workers. And new evils emerge. Young children are depended on for working the night shift because the strength of the adult men would be deteriorated if they had to work the entire night. (How ironic that men would be exhausted working the night shift, therefore children are better suited for the task?) Other exploitations occur in the way of kids having to work a double if their relief does not show up to work the next shift, and holding the shift longer to realize any benefits of the increased number of laborers that can be obtained over the first hour or two of shift switch. Marx tries to point out all the fallacies in the capitalists’ objections to ending the employment of children over the night shift.

"5. The Struggle for a Normal Working Day. Laws for the Compulsory Extension of the Working Day, from the Middle of the Fourteenth to the End of the Seventeenth Century"

Ideally a capitalist would have an individual worker producing 24 hours a day with only so much rest time as the worker needed to continue to function. The worker is nothing more to the capitalist than labor-power and a means to accumulate surplus-value and so the worker’s personal time means nothing to the capitalist, moreover the length of the individual worker’s life means nothing to capital, except that it has extracted the most surplus value from that individual as possible. Yet according to Marx, having this attitude is a double-edge sword in that if the capitalist had his way and exploited the worker to this extent, he would in essence be killing his own workforce. If this process yields a more favorable proportion of surplus labor to necessary labor time, then the capitalist should reap advantage of its workers, but at the same time keep in mind the need to replace the worker the next day. Hence, capital spent a good number of years absorbing the available workforce. Once all available labor power has been absorbed and is working, then capital has to regard providing the proper means for the workforce to not only regenerate their own commodity, labor-power, for resale each day, but also has to provide enough means of subsistence in wages to allow the worker to procreate bring a new generation of available labor power to the plate. This is the point at which capital realizes that the value of labor-power (the worker) includes all of the commodities that go into keeping the worker alive. In the end, it will be more expensive for the capitalist to replace a worker than to keep one sustained adequately. Ultimately it is in capital’s best interest to not have an individual work 24 hours a day with only necessary breaks but to have a work day that is short enough to sustain healthy strong labor-power. Marx cites several different economists arguing on behalf of both parties (Capitalists and the Proletariat) as he sums up the literature that has affected the different legislations in place at different times limiting the working day, sets aside standard times for meals, and prevents children from working obscenely long shifts. “Establishment of a normal working day is the result of centuries of struggle between the capitalist and the worker” (382).

[edit] Chapter 11: The Rate and Mass of Surplus-Value

Having explained the rate of surplus-value earlier in Ch. 9, Marx focuses this chapter on the mass of surplus-value. The mass of surplus-value is completely dependent on the number of workers under the capitalist's control. We know that the rate of surplus value is equal to \frac{S}{V} or the \frac{\mbox{Surplus Labor Time}}{\mbox{Necessary Labor Time}} or the \frac{\mbox{Rate of Surplus Value}}{\mbox{Rate of Exploitation}}. To increase this rate, the capitalist simply has to work his workers longer hours. This is simply a rate dependent on the degree of exploitation of the workers. The mass of surplus-value is determined by the rate of surplus value (S/V) multiplied by the number of workers. The more exploitation that exists, the more money the capitalist will possess.

This brief chapter is filled with typical Marxist theoretical situations to explain the mass of surplus-value but the core of the chapter lies in the three laws that Marx describes dealing with the rate of surplus-value. Marx explains as his first and most fundamental law that, "the mass of surplus-value produced is equal to the amount of the variable capital advanced multiplied by the rate of surplus-value".[21] Basically, as stated above, the mass of surplus-value is totally dependent on the total numbers of workers being exploited by the same capitalist and how much exploitation is going on. The formula S = V(\frac{s}{v}) , P(\frac{a'}{a}) comes about, where s is equal to surplus value produced by the individual worker, v being equal to the variable capital advanced in the purchase of an individual labor power, V being the total amount of variable capital, P being the value of an average labor-power, and a' / a represents the degree of exploitation (surplus labor/necessary labor).[21] Marx lets it be known that under this law, that the mass of surplus-value is not constant in nature, but that a decrease in one factor can be made up by an increase in another factor, such as variable capital dropping but the exploitation of the labor-power increasing to make up for this change.

Marx's second law deals with the limitation of compensating for lacking factors. He says that the "compensation for a decrease in the number of workers employed cannot be overcome"[22] What we see is the natural tendency of capital automatically reducing the number of workers employed by the capitalist. It is important to note the average working day in terms of compensating for fluctuating factors, because it sets an absolute limit on such compensations. Marx's third law states that "The rate of surplus-value and the value of labor time, being given, it is self-evident that the greater the variable capital, the greater would be the mass of the value produced and of the surplus-value".[23] These two factors explained are completely dependent on the mass of labor performed by the worker, or better yet how heavily the worker is exploited. Marx states that this law, or the numerical value of the factors involved here, are determined by how much variable capital is advanced from the capitalist. He further suggests that we now know the capitalist divides his capital into two parts; one part on the means of production (a constant factor) and the other on the living labor-power, which is heavily exploited and forms his variable capital.

[edit] Part Four: The Production of Relative-Surplus Value

Chapters 12-15 focus on the ways in which capital seeks to increase worker productivity as a means of increasing the rate of workers' exploitation.

[edit] Chapter 12: The Concept of Relative Surplus-Value

In the beginning of this chapter, Marx provides an illustration of the working day whose length is defined, and its division between necessary labor and surplus labor is marked as well. The line, AC, looks like this:

 A - - - - - - - - - - B - - C

The section AB represents necessary labor, and the section BC represents surplus labor. He then poses the question, “How can the production of surplus-value be increased, i.e. how can surplus labor be prolonged, without any prolongation, or independently of any prolongation, of the line AC?” [24]. Marx proposes that it is in the best interest of the capitalist to divide the working day like this:

 A - - - - - - - - - B’ - B - - C

This is showing that the amount of surplus labor is increased, while the amount of necessary labor is decreased. Through this, part of the labor-time that was used by the worker for the worker is lost, and the lost time there would be used as labor-time for the benefit of the capitalist. When there is a change in the amount of necessary labor-time, and therefore an increase in surplus-value, Marx calls this relative surplus-value. (Whereas when there is an actual lengthening in the working day and surplus value is produced, this is called absolute surplus-value.) Marx then goes on to discuss what can decrease the value of labor-power. First, remember that the value of labor-power is “the labor-time necessary to produce labor-power” [25]. With this in mind, Marx says that the value of labor-power can be decreased if there is an increase in the productivity of labor. But productivity of labor cannot be increased without there first being a change in the mode of production, i.e. there must be innovations in both the technical and social conditions of the process of labor. And when the value of labor-power falls alongside an increase in the productivity of labor, commodities become cheaper. Along with this, Marx states that, as the productivity of labor increases, so, too, does the relative surplus-value; on the other hand, when there is a decrease in the productivity of labor, the relative surplus-value decreases as well. In other words, there is a direct proportion between the two things. The perpetual drive of capital according to Marx is to increase the productivity of labor, so that commodities can become cheaper. Through this process, the worker himself becomes cheaper. The reader is reminded that the capitalist is not interested in the absolute value of a commodity; instead, he is concerned with the surplus-value that is there in it, a value that is recognized through the sale of that commodity. Marx concludes that, through the increase of the productivity of labor, the aim of capitalist production “is the shortening of that part of the working day in which the worker must work for himself, and the lengthening, thereby, of the other part of the day, in which he is free to work for nothing for the capitalist” [26].

[edit] Chapter 13: Co-operation

A group working under a capitalist does as much work as another group of the same amount of people working under the same capitalist. Their skills and shortcomings balance each other out to make groups of the same number equatable. Upon dividing up groups into smaller subgroups, changes can be noticed. Marx states, "Of the six small masters, then, one would squeeze out more than the average rate of surplus-value, another less. The inequalities would cancel out for the society as a whole, but not for the individual masters." (p 441). To simplify, among individual groups, there will be stronger, more productive groups and weaker, less productive groups. However, when reexamining the subgroups as a whole, the strong balance out the weak and balance is restored. With this information Marx defines co-operation as, "When numerous workers work together side by side in accordance with a plan, whether in the same process, or in different but connected processes." (p 443). This works well for capitalists in that, social contact brings out a natural competitive nature in people which in turn produces more commodities. Co-operation also shortens the time needed to complete a certain task. Marx says, "If the labour process is complicated, then the sheer number of the co-operators permits the apportionment of various operations to different hands, and consequently their simultaneous performance. The time necessary for the completion of the whole work is thereby shortened." (p 445). The only problem for capitalists comes with payment. It is easier for a capitalist to hire fewer people and pay them for a longer period of time than to pay many workers for a short amount of time. In essence, the amount of capital a capitalist has to spare for payment affects how many laborers he can hire at any given time. With co-operation also comes resistance. The larger a group, the more likely they are to resist conditions implemented by the capitalist and so the more the capitalist must overcome their resistance. Marx also makes the point to say, "It is not because he is a leader of industry that a man is a capitalist; on the contrary, he is a leader of industry because he is a capitalist." (p 450). Marx concludes by showing an example of co-operation that many are familiar with: the creation of the pyramids. As the food grown in the Nile valley belonged to the king, he was able to commission a large number of people to work in co-operation with one another to create the pyramids in a very short amount of time.

[edit] Chapter 14: The Division of Labour and Manufacture

In section I, “The Dual Origin of Manufacture” Marx identifies two ways in which manufacture originates. The first method occurs when a series of workers with different trades are brought together to work for one capitalist under the same roof, in such a way that a single product passes from one worker to the next. Under this method tradesmen find themselves making only one type of product: “so that a locksmith working for a carriage company would make locks only for carriages when he used to make locks for a variety of different products ”.[27]. The second form occurs when a capitalist hires a number of workers, each worker making an entire product himself. Under the external circumstance of requiring a need to speed up production this method changes so that each worker is given a specific task within the making of a product”.[28]. Isolated jobs on each commodity can start to be assigned to one worker and a division of labour can be created in this manner. In section 2, “The Specialized Worker and His Tools” Marx argues that a worker who performs only one task throughout his life will perform his job at a faster and more productive rate, forcing Capital to favor the specialized worker to the traditional craftsmen”.[29]. In this section Marx also demonstrates that a specialized worker doing only one task can use a more specialized tool, which cannot do many jobs but can do the one job well, in a more efficient manner than a traditional craftsman using a multi-purpose tool on any specific task ”.[30]. Marx considers this a basic element of manufacture. In Section 3, “The Two Fundamental Forms of Manufacture- Heterogeneous and Organic” Marx argues that the production of various commodities produces a hierarchy of skilled and unskilled labor. Skilled labor requires large amounts of training or skill and tends to command a higher value of labor-power, while unskilled labor, which any man can do, takes little to no training and commands a lower value of labor-power”.[31]. Keeping these highly specialized workers focused on keeping there highly valued job skills along with keeping them divided from their trade as a whole making of one commodity further devalues there labor power to each of them. Also one item with several menial processes (each assigned to one worker) helps to divide the workers from the value of their own labor power. In section 4, “The Division of Labour in Manufacture and the Division of Labour in Society” Marx argues that the division of labor in society has existed long before capitalism. However, Marx sees the division of labour within a factory or workshop as something totally unique to the capitalist mode of production”.[32]. While physiological and social circumstances may mediate the division of labour in society, it is the need to produce surplus value which creates the need for a division of labour within manufacture. In section 5, “The Capitalist Character of Manufacture” Marx considers the way in which a division of labour within manufacture limits the mind and education of a worker. Marx also points to the revolution of machinery as a way to increase surplus-value by increasing the productivity of each worker thereby reducing the number of unskilled workers necessary.

[edit] Chapter 15: Machinery and Large-Scale Industry

[edit] 1. Development of Machinery

In this section, Marx explains the significance of machinery to capitalists and how it is applied to the work force. The goal of introducing machinery into the work force is to increase productivity and not to decrease the toil of the worker. When productivity is increased, the commodity being produced is cheapened. Relative surplus value is amplified because machinery shortens the part of the day that the worker works for his or her means of subsistence and increases the time that the worker produces for the capitalist. As discussed in previous chapters, when the time it takes for the worker to achieve there means of subsistence decreases, the more time they will spend working for the capitalist.

At this point, Marx discusses the difference between tools and machines and their application to the process of production. Marx claims that many experts, whether they are trained in mathematics, economics or experts in mechanics see no difference between tools and machines. He claims that they “ call a tool a simple machine and a machine a complex tool” (Marx 492). Marx continues to elaborate on this definition problem, explaining that some people distinguish between a tool and a machine “ by saying that in the case of the tool, man is the motive power, whereas the power behind the machine is a natural force independent of man, for instance an animal, water, wind and so on” (Marx 493). The flaw with this approach, when defining tool from machine, is illustrated when Marx points out that this argument would indicate that a plow, which is powered by an animal, would be considered to be a machine and Claussen’s circular loom, which is able to weave at a tremendous speed, is in fact powered by one worker and there fore considered to be a tool. Marx defines the machine on page 495 of capital volume I when he says “ The machine, therefore, is a mechanism that, after being set in motion, performs with its tools the same operation as the worker formerly did with similar tools. Whether the motive power is derived from man, or in turn from a machine, makes no difference here.”

There are three parts to fully developed machinery:

  • 1. The motor mechanism powers the mechanism. Be it a steam engine, water wheel or a person’s caloric engine.
  • 2. The transmitting mechanism, wheels, screws, and ramps and pulleys. These are the moving parts of the machine.
  • 3. The working machine uses itself to sculpt whatever it was built to do.

Marx believes the working machine is the most important part of developed machinery. The working machine is what began the industrial revolution of the eighteenth century and continues to turn craft into an industry.

The Machine is able to replace a worker, who works at one specific job with one tool, with a mechanism that accomplishes the same task, but with many similar tools and at a much faster rate. One machine doing one specific task soon turns into a fleet of co-operating machines accomplishing the entire process of production. This aspect of automation enables the capitalist to replace large numbers of human workers with machines. It also enables capitalist to choose their human workforce to a much larger pool of available workers. The worker no longer need be skilled in a particular trade because their job has been reduced to oversight and maintenance of their mechanical successors.

The development of machinery is an interesting cycle where inventors started inventing machines to complete necessary tasks. The machine making industry grew larger and worker’s efforts started focusing toward building machines. With so many machines being developed, the need for new machines to create old machines increased. For example, the spinning machine started a need for printing and dying, and the designing of the cotton gin. This creation started the building of machines by other machines. “Without steam engines, the hydraulic press could not have been made. Along with the press, came the mechanical lathe and an iron cutting machine. Labor assumes a material mode of existence which necessitates the replacement of human force by natural forces” (Marx 508).

[edit] 2. The Value Transferred by Machinery to the Product

As we have seen in the previous section, the machine does not replace the tool, which is powered by man. The tool multiplies and expands into the working machine that is created by man. Workers now go to work not to handle the tools of production but to work with the machine, which handles the tools. It is clear that large-scale industry increase the productivity of labor to an extraordinary degree by incorporating its fast paced efficiency with in the process of production. What is not as clear is that this new increase in productivity does not require an equal increase in expended labor by the worker. Machinery creates no new value. The machine accumulates value from the labor, which went into producing it, and it merely transfers its value into the product it’s producing until its value is used up.

Only labor power, which is bought by capitalists, can create new value. Machinery transfers its value into the product at a rate, which is dependent upon how much the total value of the machinery is. “ The less value it gives up, the more productive it is, and the more its services approach those rendered by natural forces” (Marx 512). The general rule of machinery is that the labor used to create it must be less than how much human work it replaces when it is used in the process of production. Other wise, the machinery would not be effective in raising surplus value and instead depreciate it. This is why some machinery is not chosen to replace actual human workers. It would not be cost effective.

[edit] 4. The Factory

Marx begins this section with two descriptions of the factory as a whole.

“Combined co-operation of many orders of workpeople, adult and young, in tending with assiduous skill, a system of productive machines, continuously impelled by a central power” (the prime mover); on the other hand, as “a vast automaton, composed of various mechanical and intellectual organs, acting in uninterrupted concert for the production of a common object, all of them being subordinate to a self-regulated moving force.” (544-545)

This twofold description shows the characteristics of the relationship between the collective body of labor power and the machine. In the first description, the workers, or collective labor power, are viewed as separate entities from the machine. In the second description, the machine is the dominant force, with the collective labor acting as mere appendages of the self operating machine. Marx uses the latter description to display the characteristics of the modern factory system under capitalism.

In the factory, the tools of the worker disappear, and the worker’s skill is passed on to the machine. The division of labor and specialization of skills re-appear in the factory, only now as a more exploitative form of capitalist production. Work is still organized into co-operative groups. Work in the factory usually consists of two groups, people who are employed on the machines and those who attend to the machines. The third group, outside of the factory, is a superior class of workers, trained in the maintenance and repair of the machines.

Factory work begins at childhood to ensure that a person may adapt to the systematic movements of the automated machine, therefore increasing productivity for the capitalist. Marx describes this work as being extremely exhausting to the nervous system and void of intellectual activity. Factory work robs workers of basic working conditions like clean air, light, space, and protection. Marx ends the section by asking if jourier was wrong when he called factories ‘mitigated jails’?

[edit] 5. The Struggle between Worker and Machine

In the beginning of this section Marx recounts the introduction of machinery and the resistance among workers that followed it. Marx does not criticize the machines themselves or technology, but the capitalist system that envelops the machines. He states that,

“It took both time and experience before workers learned to distinguish between machinery and their employment by capital, and therefore to transfer their attacks from the material instruments of production to the form of society which utilizes those instruments.” (554)

Marx describes the machine as the instrument of labor for the capitalists’ material mode of existence. The machine competes with the worker, diminishing the use-value of the worker’s labor-power. Marx also points out that with the advance in technology of machines led to the substitution of less skilled work for more skilled work which ultimately led to a change in wages. During the progression of machinery the numbers of skilled workers decreased, while child labor flourished, increasing profits for the capitalist.

[edit] 6. The Compensation Theory, With Regard to the Workers Displaced by Machinery

In this section, Marx sets forth to illuminate the error within the compensation theory of the political economists. According to this theory, the displacement of workers by machinery will necessarily “set free” an equal stable, amount of variable capital previously used for the purchase of labor-power and remains available for the same purpose. However, Marx argues that the introduction of machinery is simply a shift of variable capital to constant capital. The capital “set free” cannot be used for compensation since the displacement of variable capital available becomes embodied in the machinery purchased[33]. The capital that may become available for the compensation will always be less than the total amount of capital previously used to purchase labor-power before the addition of machinery. Furthermore, the remainder of variable capital available is directed towards hiring workers with the expertise skills to operate new machinery. Therefore the conversion of the greater part of the total capital is now used as constant capital, a reduction of variable capital necessarily follows. As a result of machinery, displacedworkers are not so quickly compensated by employment in other industries but are forced into an expanding labor-market at a disadvantage and available for greater capitalist exploitation without the ability to procure the means of subsistence for survival[34]. Furthermore, Marx argues that the introduction of machinery may increase employment in other industries, yet this expansion “has nothing in common with the so-called theory of compensation”[35]. Greater productivity will necessarily generate an expansion of production into peripheral fields that provide raw materials. Conversely machinery introduced to industries that produce raw materials will lead to an increase in those industries that consume them. The production of greater surplus-value leads to greater wealth of the ruling classes, an increase in the labor-market, and consequently the establishment of new industries. As such Marx cites the growth of the domestic service industry equated to greater servitude by the exploited classes[36].

[edit] 7. Repulsion and Attraction of Workers Through The Development of Machine Production, Crises in the Cotton Industry

The political economist apology for the displacement of workers by machinery asserts that there is a corresponding increase in employment. Marx is quick to cite the example of the silk industry in which an actual decrease of employment appears simultaneously with an increase of existing machinery. On the other hand an increase in the number of factory workers employed is the result of “the gradual annexation of neighboring branches of industry” and “the building of more factories or the extension of old factories in a given industry.”[37] Furthermore, Marx argues that an increase in factory workers is relative since the displacement of workers creates a proportionately wider gap between the increase of machinery and a proportionate decrease of labor required to operate that machinery.[38] The constant expansion of capitalism and ensuing technical advances leads to extension of markets until it reaches all corners of the globe thus creating cycles of economic prosperity and crisis.[39] Finally, the “repulsion and attraction” of workers therefore results as a cycle in which there is a constant displacement of workers by machinery which necessarily leads to increased productivity followed by a relative expansion of industry and higher employment of labor. This sequence renews itself as all components of the cycle lead to novel technological innovation for "replacing labor-power."[40]

[edit] Part Five: The Production of Absolute and Relative Surplus-Value

Chapters 16-18 examine how the capitalist strategies for the production of both absolute and relative surplus-value are combined and can function simultaneously.

[edit] Chapter 16: The Rise of Surplus Value

Marx describes the process of taking the workers individual productive actions and making them a collective effort of many workers. This action takes the worker further away from the actual production of the commodity and then allows the capitalist to use the worker only to create surplus value. The surplus value is increased first through absolute methods, such as extending the work day, then through relative methods, such as increasing worker productivity. These actions are the general foundations of capitalism as described by Marx.

The worker’s transformation from producer of commodities for use in survival to producer of surplus value is necessary in the progression to capitalism. In production outside the capitalist system the worker produces everything they need to survive. When the worker moves beyond producing what they need to survive, they can provide their work for a wage and create part of some product in return for a wage to buy what they need to survive. Capitalism takes advantage of this extra time by paying the worker a wage that allows them to survive but is less than the value the same worker creates. Through large scale manufacturing and economies of scale the workers are placed progressively further away from manufacturing products themselves and only function as part of a whole collective that creates the commodities. This changes the concept of productive labor from the production of commodities to the production of surplus value (pg. 644). The worker is only productive to the capitalist if they can maximize the surplus value the capitalist is earning.

Not simply content with the transformation of the worker from a creator of commodities to creator of surplus value, capitalist must devise new ways to increase the surplus that he is receiving. The first, or absolute, way the capitalist can increase surplus value is through the prolongation of the working day so the worker has more time to create value (pg. 646). The second, or relative, way the capitalist can increase surplus value is to revolutionize changes in the production method (pg. 646). If the worker can only produce the means for himself in the time he works during the day there would be no extra time for him to create surplus value for the capitalist. The capitalist must then either enable the worker to complete the paid work time more quickly through relative means, or he must increase the work day in absolute terms. Without enabling unpaid work to exist the capitalist system would not be able to sustain itself.

With surplus labor resting on a natural basis, there are no natural obstacles preventing one man from imposing his labor burden on another. As a worker looks into the possible options of getting out of capitalist exploitation or the initial “animal condition”, one of the obvious options is becoming a capitalist himself. This is called socialized labor which exists when the surplus labor of one worker becomes necessary for the existence of another. Marx mentions two natural conditions of wealth that are helpful in understanding the progression of socialized labor over time. The two conditions are natural wealth in the means of subsistence and natural wealth in the instruments of labor. Over time, society has moved more from the former to the latter. It wasn’t that long ago that the majority of society produced for themselves and didn’t have to be concerned about producing surplus labor for others. We did labor for others, but it was not in effort to create surplus value, it was to help others.

Marx uses the Egyptians as an example to illustrate a society’s potential when there is extra time that doesn’t have to be used toward creating surplus value. The Egyptians lived in a very fertile land (natural subsistence wealth) so could raise children at a very low cost. This is the main reason why the population grew so large. One might think all the great Egyptian structures were possible because of the large population, but is due to the availability of labor time. In regards to capitalism, you might think that a greater natural wealth of subsistence would result in greater growth and capitalist production (like the Egyptians), but that is not the case. So why is capitalism so strong in many countries that don’t have excess natural resources? The answer is the necessity of bringing a natural force under the control of society (irrigation in Persia and India, flow of water in Egypt, etc.) As Marx says, “favourable conditions provide the possibility, not the reality of surplus labour.”

Marx displays an example of surplus labor occurring in these favorable conditions in the case of the East Indies. The inhabitants would be able to produce enough to satisfy all of his needs with only twelve working hours per week. This provides for more than enough leisure time until capitalist production takes hold. Then he may be required to work six days per week to satisfy his needs – there can be no explanation of why it is necessary for him to provide the extra five days of surplus labor.

Marx then critiques famed economist David Ricardo and the lack of addressing the issue of surplus-value. Ricardo does not take the time to discuss the origin of surplus-value and side-stepped the entire issue altogether. Agreeing with classical economists, John Stuart Mill finds that the productive power, surplus value, is the source of profits, but adds that the necessities of life take less time to produce than is required by society. Therefore, this becomes the reason capital will realize a profit. Mill goes on to assert that profit can only be gleaned from productive power and not exchange which falls in line with Marx’s theories.

The next critique of Mill goes on to the percentage that is gained from the laborer. Marx finds it to be “absolutely false” in the fact that the percentage of surplus labor will always be more than the profits. This is due to the amount of capital invested. Following his conclusions, Marx calls Mill’s ideas an optical illusion as he looks into the advancing of capital. Mill looks at laborers and considers them to be a form of capitalist – they are advancing the capitalist their labor ahead of time and receiving it at the end of the project for more of a share. Marx hits the idea out with the analogy of the American peasant being his own slave as he is doing forced labor for himself.

Karl Marx examined surplus value and showed it to be a necessity in capitalism. This surplus value is derived from the difference between the value the worker creates and the wage he earns. Chapter 16 looked into the ways in which the capitalist is able to increase surplus-value and takes a direct attack against economists David Ricardo and John Stuart Mill.

[edit] Chapter 17 Changes of Magnitude in the price of Labor-Power and in Surplus-Value

The Value of Labor power, also known as wage, is the first thing that Marx begins to re-explain in the opening of the chapter stressing that it is equal to the quantity of the “necessaries of life habitually required by the average laborer.” By re-stressing the importance of this concept he is building a foundation on which he can begin to elaborate his argument on the changing price of labor. In order to make his argument, Marx states that he will leave out two certain factors of change (the expenses of labor power that differ with each mode of production and the diversity of labor power between men and women, children and adults) and that he will also be making 2 assumptions. The two assumptions made are first, the commodities are sold at their values, and second, the price of labor-power occasionally rises above its value, but never falls beneath it.

Given these assumptions Marx begins to formulate his argument by first establishing the three determinants of the price of labor power. These three determinants, or circumstances as Marx calls them, are: the length of the working day, the normal intensity of labor, and the productiveness of labor. Formulating these three circumstances into different combinations of variables and constants Marx begins to clarify the changes in Magnitude in the price of labor-power. The majority of Chapter XVII is dedicated to the chief combinations of these three factors.

“I. Length of the working day and Intensity of labor constant; Productiveness of labor variable.”

Starting out with these assumptions Marx explains that there are three laws that determine the value of labor-power. The first of these three laws states that a working day of given amount of hours will always produce the same amount of value. This value will always be a constant, no matter the productiveness of labor, or the price of the commodity produced. The second states that the surplus-value and labor-power are negatively correlated or that when surplus-value increases a unit and value stays the same labor-power must decrease one unit also. The third of these laws is that a change in surplus-value presupposes a change in that of the labor-power.

Given these three laws Marx explains how the productiveness of labor, being the variable, changes the magnitude of labor-value. Marx explains saying “a change in the magnitude of surplus-value, presupposes a movement in the value of labour-power, which movement is brought about by a variation in the productiveness of labour.” This variation in the productiveness of labor is what eventually leads to the developing change in value, which is then divided by either the laborers, through extra labor-value, or the capitalist, through extra surplus value.

“II. Working-day constant; Productiveness of labor constant; Intensity of labor.” The Intensity of labor is the expenditure that the laborer puts into a commodity. The increase in the intensity of labor results in the increase of value that the labor is producing. This increase that the laborer is producing is again divided amongst the capitalist and laborer in the form of either surplus-value or an increase in the value of labor power. Though they may both increase simultaneously the addition to the labor may not be an addition if the extra payment received from his increase in intensity does not cover the wear and tear it has on the laborer.

“III. Productivity and Intensity of Labor Constant; Length of Working Day Variable.” In this example it is possible to change the length of the working day by either lengthening of shortening the time spent at work. Leaving the other two variables constant, reducing the length of the work day leaves the labor-power’s value the same as it was before. This reducing of the length of the work day will reduce the surplus labor and surplus value dropping it below its value.

The other option in changing the workday is to lengthen it. If the labor-power stays the same with a longer workday then the surplus-value will increase relatively and absolutely. The relative value of labor-power will fall even though it will not absolutely. With the lengthening of the workday and the nominal price staying the same, the price of labor-power possibly could fall below its value. The value is estimated to be what is produced by the worker and a longer workday will affect the production and therefore the value. It is fine to assume the other variables stay constant, but a change in the work day with the others constant will not result in the outcomes supposed here. A change in the work day by the capitalists will most definitely affect the productivity and intensity of the labor.

“IV. Simultaneous Variations in the Duration, Productivity and Intensity of Labor.”

In the real world it is almost never possible to isolate each of the aspects of labor. Two or even three of the variables may vary and in different aspects. One may move up while another moves down, or in the same direction. The combinations are endless, but may be characterized by the first three examples. However, Marx limits his analysis to two cases.

“(1) Diminishing productivity of labor with a simultaneous lengthening of the workday.” This example is one where workers are working longer hours paying less attention or dedication on the job and productivity is in turn reduced; or productivity decreases, increasing the workday to achieve the same output. Therefore, the magnitude of these changes will continue on its path causing longer and longer workdays with lower productivity until the system can sustain no more.
“(2) Increasing intensity and productivity of labor with simultaneous shortening of the working day.” Productivity and intensity are closely related and offer similar outcomes. Higher productivity and intensity will increase the workers output allowing for the workday to be shorter as they will achieve their necessary subsistence. The working day can shrink multiple times so long as the other elements live up to their sides of the bargain.
The price of labor-power is affected by many things that can be broken down. The three main elements of intensity, productivity and length of workday were broken down and analyzed separately and then together. From the examples presented it is possible to see what would happen in any and all situations.

[edit] Part Six: Wages

Chapters 19-22 examine the ways in which capital manipulates the money wage as ways of both concealing exploitation and of extorting increased amounts of unpaid labor from workers.

[edit] Chapter 19: The Transformation of the Value (and Respective Price) of Labour-Power into Wages

In this chapter Marx brings into perspective how wages fit into the picture of capitalism. Marx begins by noticing how oblivious society is when it speaks "of the value of labour and call its expression in money its necessary or natural price"(675). A laborer is interested primarily in meeting his means of subsistence; therefore, he is easily exploited by the capitalist, who, is more interested in paying him as little as possible than endowing him with an equal exchange for the value he creates. As selling this labor-power is a way of ensuring the means of subsistence, laborers are willing to sell their labor power to a capitalist, for whom he will serve a specific function. However, Marx shows how the capitalist uses the wage he pays to his worker to disguise what is actually being paid out. He begins by showing us how payment works under three different systems. First under the old corvee system or feudal system the laborer understands that the labor he does on his land is for him-self and the labor he does on the land of his lord belongs to his lord. There is no misunderstanding of what the laborer is producing for himself and the lord. The same is true for the slave. Although some of his labor is for his means of subsistence, the slave knows his labor is mostly surplus for his master. However, to the wage laborer it appears as though he is being paid the value of his labor. Unfortunately for the laborer what he is being paid for is his labor power, not the amount of labor he produced. Therefore, despite the fact the laborer thinks he is being paid for all his labor he is actually only creating surplus value for the capitalist. “All the notions of justice held by both the worker and the capitalist, all the mystifications of the capitalist mode of production, all capitalism’s illusions about freedom, all the apologetic tricks of vulgar economics, have as their basis the form of appearance discussed above, which makes the actual relation invisible, and indeed presents to the eye the precise opposite of that relation (680). This is how the capitalist is able to further exploit the worker when it comes to paying him a wage.

[edit] Chapter 20: Time-Wages

The first fundamental form of wage that Marx analyzes take the form of time-wages. The sale of labor-power is always for a definite period of time[41]. This time may be that of a day, week, etc. The money that the worker receives at the end of this period is referred to by Marx as his nominal wage[42]. According to the length of the working day, the same daily or weekly (nominal) wage may represent drastically different prices of labor[43]. This average price of labor can be determined by dividing the average daily value of labor-power (nominal wage) by the number of hours in the working day[44].A rise in the number of hours in a working day correlates to a fall in the price of labor. This is a means of lowering the price of labor independent of the workers daily or weekly nominal wage. Even if the wage of the worker rises, it can still remain constant or even fall depending upon a rise in the hours worked[45].

Hourly wages may now be employed by the capitalist to obscure and even annihilate the connection between the value of the workers' labor-power and the value of his labor[46]. This occurs when there ceases to be a set number of hours in the workday. The capitalist can now employ the worker for a period of the working day where the worker creates surplus value, while not employing him long enough so that he expends enough labor time to provide for his own subsistence. For the worker then to provide the means of subsistence for himself, he must work extra hours. Marx notes the dual benefits to the capitalist in this situation, "If one man does the work of 1 1/2 or 2 men, the supply of labor increases, although the supply of labor-power on the market remains constant. The competition thus created between the workers allows the capitalist to force down the price of labor, while the fall in price allows him, on the other hand, to force up the hours of work even further[47]."

Time wages encourage the belief, both to the capitalist and the worker, that labor is being bought directly, when in reality it is the labor-power that is being bought and subsequently exploited.

[edit] Chapter 21: Piece-Wages

Marx explains the exploitative nature of the piece-wage system. Under this system workers are paid a pre-determined amount for each piece they produce, creating a modified form of the time-wage system. A key difference is in the fact that the piece-wage system provides an exact measure of the intensity of labor. Meaning that the capitalists’ know about how long it takes to produce one piece of finished product. Those who cannot meet these standards of production will not be allowed to keep their jobs. This system also allows for middlemen to usurp positions between the capitalists and laborers. These middlemen make their money solely from paying labor less than capitalists are actually allotting, thus, bringing about worker on worker exploitation. Logic would lead a laborer to believe that straining one’s labor power “as intensely as possible” works in one’s own interests because the more efficiently they produce the more they will be paid. Therefore, the workday will lengthen to the extent that worker’s allow and necessitate. However, prolongation in the workday requires the price of labor to fall. Marx elucidates that, “The piece-wage therefore has a tendency, while raising the wages of individuals above the average, to lower this average itself”, and “it is apparent that the piece-wage is the form of wage most appropriate to the capitalist mode of production.” Marx gives examples of the Weaving Industry around the time of the Anti-Jacobin War where "piece-wages had fallen so low that in spite of the very great lengthening of the working day, the daily wage was then lower than it had been before." So in this example we are able to see how piece-wages do nothing but decrease the value of labor and better disguise the true way the workers are exploited. [48].

[edit] Part Seven: The Process of Accumulation of Capital

Chapters 23-25 explore the ways in which profits are used to recreate capitalist class relations on an ever expanding scale and the ways in which this expansion of capitalism creates periodic crises for capitalist accumulation. For Marx, these crises in accumulation are also always crises in the perpetuation of the class relations necessary for capitalist production and so are also opportunities for revolutionary change.

[edit] Chapter 23: Simple Reproduction

Just as a society cannot stop consuming, it cannot stop producing. “Every social process of production,” writes Marx, “is at the same time a process of reproduction.” [49] This is one of Marx’s most important points, for capital must be seen as a forever developing value. Since labor power and the means of production are constantly consumed in the process of production, they must be reproduced for production to continue.

Simple reproduction refers to a capitalist consuming all of the surplus value created and reinvesting the same amount of capital during each cycle. This causes production levels to remain constant.

Marx pauses here to clarify two points. First, though workers are seemingly paid in money, in actuality they are paid in wages. Off the clock, in order for workers to obtain part of their means of subsistence, they must give these wages back to the capitalist class. “The transaction,” Marx writes, “is veiled by the commodity-form of the product and the money-form of the commodity.” [50]

Second, Marx points out that the capitalist must produce surplus value in order for production to continue. If surplus value is not created, and the capitalist keeps advancing capital (and consuming) from his own pocket, he will eventually go broke. Simple reproduction therefore “converts all capital into accumulated capital.” [51]

Part of the cycle of simple reproduction is the replication of class relations. Workers receive enough to keep them at work and purchase their means of subsistence. “The worker always leaves the process in the same state as he entered it – a personal source of wealth, but deprived of any means of making that wealth a reality for himself.” [52] Since there is nothing left over after purchasing their means of subsistence, they must sell their labor power again. The wages paid to him are for the labor power consumed last pay period, so the worker is providing credit to the capitalist without any additional interest or return. In this way workers remain poor and remain at work. Meanwhile, the capitalists advance capital, create surplus value, and are able to profit and reinvest. All of the surplus value doesn’t remain with the capitalist, he must spend it on more means of production and this keeps other capitalists able to create surplus value for themselves. Marx also points out that all initial capital is transformed into accumulated capital – appropriated from the surplus value of the labor. Used to purchase new but greater means of production uses up the surplus in a continual cycle. The worker, selling his labor power, alienates it from himself and in doing so, produces more surplus value for the capitalist. The capitalist, in turn, produces the wage laborer – by the simple process of buying and selling from one another. Here lies the basis for the class struggle.

[edit] Chapter 24: The Transformation of Surplus-Value into Capital

In Chapter 24, Marx explains how capitalist are able to transform surplus value into more capital. Marx begins by expounding upon the accumulation of capital, which he defines as “the employment of surplus-value as capital, or its reconversion into capital.” [53] Marx uses the illustration of a Master yarn Spinner to demonstrate how capitalist use more money to invest in more means of production and labor-power. Thus, Marx is able to further reiterate that, “accumulation requires to the transformation of a portion of the surplus product into capital.” [54] Marx further elaborates that the reason why surplus-value can be transformed into capital is because the surplus product “already comprises the material components of a new quantity of capital." [55]

Capitalist expansion, according to Marx, requires additional labor-power. Marx explains that the “mechanism of capitalist production” is constantly producing and reproducing a working class that depends on wages to survive, thus replenishing the capitalist need for labor-power and thereby aiding capitalist expansion. [55] Labor power used to reproduce the worker cannot be done without always creating more surplus value that benefits the capitalist. The basic biological requirements of eating and sex will continue to work to the capitalist’s advantage, creating a replacement labor force without the capitalist having to supervise this. Marx states that what is true of all accumulated capital in comparison to the addition of capital made by it is that “the original capital continues to reproduce itself and to produce surplus-value alongside the newly formed capital.” [56]

Marx lists three results of the original transformation of money: (1) that the product belongs to the capitalist and not the worker; (2) that the value of this product includes, apart from the value of the capital advance; a surplus-value which costs the worker labour but the capitalist nothing, and which nonetheless becomes the legitimate property of the capitalist; (3) that the worker has retained his labour-power and can sell it anew if he finds another buyer. [57]

Marx, therefore concludes, that even in simple reproduction all capital is made into accumulated capital; despite the fact that the capital originally advanced begins to diminish when compared to the directly accumulated capital. [58]

[edit] Chapter 25, Section 3 & 4: The General Law of Capitalist Accumulation

Composition of capital is broken into two parts – labor value and means of production. The organic composition is a basic split between the two with each remaining the same. This leads to requiring more labor power with higher wages. When machinery is introduced to increase productivity, the composition of capital undergoes a qualitative change. The composition of capital undergoes a qualitative change when the total social capital of a society grows, or accumulates. This accumulation presupposes an increase in productivity and efficiency in the affected industries and consequently produces a decreased need for labor in general. If productivity increases (i.e. if there are more machines that take the place of human labor) then there is less employment; for even if the total quantity of labor employed increases, it is in a “constantly diminishing proportion” to the average amount needed by capital for the valorization process. Thus accumulation creates an industrial reserve army of labor that is available for hire. Conversely, if productivity and accumulation is stagnant, or the cost-benefit ratio of machine power to labor power is unfavorable, there exists a greater need for labor to create surplus value. But this is not what a capitalist wants and is antithetical to the ethos of capitalist production. What a capitalist wants is increased productivity and thus the increased production of relative surplus value. By making fewer workers (in proportion to the total population and need for labor) work more productively, and thus put more of their labor time into producing surplus value, there is less need to employ more workers, and the superfluous workers already employed can be discarded. Marx states that this creates a division in the working class of a nation; the forcibly unemployed industrial reserve army already mentioned, versus an employed class of workers who are chronically underpaid and overworked. This affects wages in two ways. If there is a high level of industrial reserve workers in proportion to a low level of employed workers, then obviously demand for labor is low and thus wages are low. Conversely, if there are few in the industrial reserve and many people employed, thus accelerating accumulation, then demand for labor is high and wages are high. However, this upward trend in employment always reaches a critical mass when too much is produced and there are not enough consumers to absorb it, and thus products (and therefore surplus value) go to waste. Then workers are “set free,” wages drop for those still employed, and the cycle begins anew. At a point where the labor costs become too high, the capitalist will stop transforming money into capital and cease production. This leads to more unemployment, which drives wages down once again. The end result will be to produce both bigger capitalists and more poor workers. This is the workers paradox; work harder, produce more, but get fired in the end because they produced too much. As the total social wealth of a nation grows, so does its population, and as its population suffers through the abovementioned cycle, the more people become unemployed due to their own productivity. That is essentially the absolute general law of capitalist accumulation.

[edit] Part Eight: So-Called Primitive Accumulation

Chapters 26-33 concern the history and origins of capitalism and of capitalist class relations.

[edit] Chapter 26: The Secret of Primitive Accumulation

In Chapters 26-31, Marx’s theories on primitive accumulation are based solely on actual historical experience, differing from other theorist’s “mystical” or “utopian” ideals. Primitive accumulation is the accumulation of wealth that takes place prior to the capitalist era of production and provides the starting point that makes possible subsequent capitalist accumulation. Marx’s theories on primitive accumulation go hand in hand with the expropriation of the masses, which thus holds the “secret” of primitive accumulation. Moreover, primitive accumulation emerges from a history of systematic violence and brutality, rather than from the simple hard work and thrift of a few would-be capitalists. In addition, monetary accumulation is not enough to suffice capitalist society. There is a strong need for “free workers” who are willing, able, and needing to work for a monetary wage. The “freeing” of serfs and slaves from their feudal lords, also “frees” them of their land and homes i.e. their means of production and means of subsistence. “So-called primitive accumulation, therefore, is nothing else than the historical process of divorcing the producer from the means of production.”[65] Also from Marx, “Primitive accumulation plays approximately the same role in political economy as original sin does in theology" (Marx 1977, p. 873) This dilemma created a duality of classes; workers and capitalist.

[edit] Chapter 27: The Expropriation of the Agricultural Population from the Land

The last third of the 15th Century marked the beginning of the rise of the capitalist mode of production and the initial creation of the working class. But before the rise of this capitalistic society, feudalism ruled England. Though completely gone by the end of the fourteenth century, feudalism set the stage on which the agricultural worker’s land and rights would be seized. Under this society, Marx explains, the population largely consisted of “free peasant proprietors.” [59] These wage-laborers consisted of peasants and partly independent agricultural workers (or yeomen) who, in addition to their wages were provided with cottages and land to work for their own subsistence. Additionally, they had the right to use the common land, where they could raise cattle, timber, fire-wood, and turf. But, by the end of the fifteenth century the expropriation of the peasantry from the land – and the various methods of primitive accumulation – had begun. At this time, the peasants were forced to migrate to barren, coarse lands while their former communal lands became the private property of a few soon-to-be capitalist landowners. The driving force behind this takeover of land was the rapid technological advances in the manufacturing of textiles and the accompanying higher prices for wool. The peasants’ cottages were razed to the ground and their land taken up for sheep-walks. Thus the land was usurped from the peasants strictly for the purpose of industry, only to later be turned into deer preserves, still keeping peasants from their native soil. This precedence of deer-hunting for sport over agricultural or pastoral land led to a famine in Germany [60]. A peasant was lucky to get any land at all for their own subsistence. “A few acres to the cottage would make the laborers too independent," [61] says Dr. Hunter, meaning that they would not have to participate in the exchange of capital or work for their means of subsistence if they produced all they needed for themselves. Though the peasant farmers were initially driven off the land by sheer brute force, the ‘Bills for Inclosure of Commons’ [62] was later sanctified by the Parliament in the 18th Century. This gave the power to legally enforce the ability of landowners to claim peoples’ land as private property. No longer able to provide their own means of subsistence without arable land or property of their own, a body of wage-laborers was created in need of employment for survival. The seized, liquidated and privately owned land then provided the means for large-scale agricultural production, which provided the market and employment for the new "free and rightless" [63] proletariat class who now depended on its industry.

[edit] Chapter 28: Bloody Legislation against the Expropriated since the End of the Fifteenth Century. The Forcing Down of Wages by Act of Parliament

The creation of the bourgeoisie, fueled by the enclosure of common lands that once sustained a vast peasant population, left these peasants and serfs, the new proletariat, to adapt to a new way of life. The old subsistent mode of production no longer existed leaving these people, as Marx puts it, “free and rightless”. Though at this point in history we see the beginnings of a bourgeoisie class, there is not yet an efficient capitalist mode of production to absorb the newly ‘created’ proletariat. Because it was not yet natural to sell ones labor for profit many became beggars and thieves. This is why at the end of the fifteenth century there is a sudden increase in the number of harsh and violent laws against vagabonds. From the early 1500s on, harsh punishment ranged from whipping and mortification to forced slavery and even beheading. Thomas More indicates that as many as 72,000 were put to death under the pretext of theft. Over generations, these violent laws made people begin to look “upon the requirements of that mode of production(Capitalism) as self evident natural laws”. And thus, the once self sufficient peasants and serfs were forced to accept giving their labor up as pure commodity in order to buy products they once produced themselves.

[edit] Chapter 29: The Genesis of the Capitalist Farmer

With an antagonizing tone in the first sentence Marx poses the original question of the entire section which is “Whence came the capitalists originally?” Marx begins this the discussion of the origin of capitalists at the same place he began the discussion of the origin of the proletariat, the other side of primitive accumulation, in the countryside with the beginning of the capitalist farmer. “…to give the place to the farmer proper, who makes his own capital breed by employing wage-laborers, and pays a part of the surplus-product, in money or in kind, to the landlord as rent.”

The process that created the proletariat also created the conditions for the new “farmer proper” to organize their farmland so that the new capitalist farmer can employ the ever increasingly cheaper and cheaper wage-labor available to him. This wage-labor continued to steadily become cheaper thanks to the fall in value of precious metals and in turn lowered wages. These lowered wages, as well as the diminished rent being paid since it was calculated on the old value of money, led to a great deal of surplus for the capitalist farmer. This great increase in the surplus due to the low wages and low amount of surplus paid to the landlord (rent) was used by Marx, through examples, to show the decreasing control of the landlords, a reorganization of the countryside from previous, which led to the increasing control of the emerging class of capitalist farmer.

[edit] Chapter 30: Impact of the Agricultural Revolution on Industry. The Creation of a Home Market for Industrial Capital

The continual, systematic expropriation of peasants from the land supplied the urban industries with a fresh mass of proletariat, in need of work, that existed completely outside of the protection of the guilds (30). The expropriation and reduction in the number of peasant farmers consequentially increased the amount of available labor-power. Expropriation resulted in a population both free from a Lord and from and means of production and subsistence. The worker found a new means of subsistence in the form of wages, obtained from his new Lord, the industrial capitalist. Marx says that to the Capitalist this was nothing short of the “direct intervention of Providence.” By divorcing much of the agricultural population from their means of subsistence, the home market was subsequently created. Because of this, their former means of subsistence now became material elements of capital, i.e. commodities that must be bought.

[edit] Chapter 31: The Genesis of the Industrial Capitalist

It is out of the ashes of feudalism, via widespread expropriation of the agricultural peoples that Industrial Capitalism springs. Deprived of their traditional means of subsistence, many of these displaced farmers and artisans found themselves faced with few options for survival, and therefore they themselves became capitalists. In this sense, workers parted with tangible property ownership in exchange for capital with no legal right to the property used for its production. The worker is deprived power over the land and goods that they are expected to maintain through forced, and waged-labor. The capitalists then required great labor forces to manage their newly amassed resources. To solve this problem, the capitalists then began a long process of enslaving people to provide this labor force. The implementation of government systems in England such as national debt, taxes, and the military assured the continuation of capitalist demand (915). This colonial system became the structure necessary for the execution of commercial wars to accumulate resources for the generation of capital via the exploitation of waged, and slave laborers. The employment of child labor and exploitation became common, as it was maximally profitable for the capitalist objective. The market for capital was of course then able to be controlled for the benefit of the capitalist. Even famine became a tool for capitalist generation in 1769-1770 when England bought up rice for the purpose of selling it at a disproportionately larger profit (917). The workers under the capitalist society are by definition vital proponents of the capitalist market. Encouraged to participate in the creation of debt, each worker participates in the creation of “joint-stock companies, the stock-exchange and modern bankocracy” (919). The international credit system conceals the source of its generation, the exploitation of slave and wage laborers. Taxpayers keep buying into these credit systems and paying taxes, but are not able to escape either system. In fact, for any person involved in this system they themselves cannot escape capital’s bloody roots (926).

[edit] Chapter 32: The Historical Tendency of Capitalist Accumulation

In this chapter, Marx is explaining the direction that Capitalist Accumulation is going, which is ultimately the downfall of capitalism through a revolution of the mass workers. Marx begins this chapter with a question, "What does the primitive accumulation of capital resolve itself into?" The answer to that question is "the dissolution of private property based on the labour of its owners, i.e expropriation of the immediate producers".[64]

The private property of the worker is essential to establish small-scale industries, and furthermore, small-scale industry is a necessary condition for the development of social production and of the free individuality of the worker. The worker is his own boss, whether if that is through cultivating their own land, or the artisan owning the tools with which he is an accomplished performer. However, we now see that a mass expropriation of the worker lays the foundation for capitalist history. Private property is now replaced with capitalist private property, by the highest form of exploitation, and we now see the shift from the days of free labour to immigrant/alien labour. Workers are turned into proletarians and their means of labour are transformed into capital by the capitalist who is exploiting the workers on a large scale. Capitalist private property is formed from the capital mode of appropriation, which has dwindled away the once existent private property that was founded on personal labour of workers.[65]

The nature of capitalism, though, brings about its own demise. In a system that "exlcudes co-operation, the social control and regulation of forces of nature, and the free development of the productive forces of society" it allows no room other for modes of production outside of its own.[66] As capitalists begin to strike down one another they eventually are faced with being expropriated by the workers through a "centralization of capitals"[67] With a working class that is strong in number and fully united, this group soon becomes "incompatible with their capitalist integument" and "the expropriators are expropriated" and the we know have a situation in which "the expropriation of a few usurpers by the mass of people".[68]

Of course, Marx stresses that the demise of capitalism does not necessarily mean the return of private property. "It does not re-establish private property, but it does indeed establish individual property on the basis of the achievements of the capitalist era: namely co-operation and the possession in common of the land and the means of production produced by labour itself." That is to say that the transformation of capitalist private property, which already sustains itself by society, into social property.

[edit] Chapter 33: The Modern Theory of Colonization

The chapter begins with the explanation of two different kinds of private property. The first "rests on the labour of the producer himself", while the second, "(rests) on the exploitation of the labour of others".[69] Marx says that the second type was a result of the only grows off the first type.[69] With the advent of colonies, capitalist nature has to take a different structure than that of "Homeland Capitalism". E.G. Wakefield said, "in the colonies capital is not a thing but a social relation between persons which is mediated through things".[70] The wage labourer of colonies is not willing to sell himself of his own free will, as many do back in the mother country, as land is plentiful and cheap if not free in the colonies. Capitalism has to turn the means of production from the individual producers into capital. This can be achieved by expropriation and heavy exploitation of the worker. If domination over the workers free will cannot be achieved, Marx then asks, "how did capital and wage-labour come into existence?"[71] This comes about through the division of workers into owners of capital and owners of labour and the workers have essentially expropriated themselves in order to accumulate capital.[72] This self-expropriation served as primitive accumulation and therefore the catalyst for capitalism in the colonies. The worker is socially dependent on the capitalist, by expropriating himself and selling himself to the capitalist in return for capital(through some artificial means<. Once thref>Marx, Karl. Capital, Volume I. Trans. Ben Fowkes. London: Penguin, 1990. 934) and the workers continue to increase in number, the mode of production will generate capital. But it is important to realize the difference in the dependence of the worker to the mother land compared to the colony. We have seen that the capitalist practice of primitive accumulation has been prescribed for use in the colonies now and also the continual expropriation of the worker.[73] Though the chapter is heavy on the establishment of colonies and the implementation of capitalist methods in the new areas, Marx makes his point fairly clear in the last paragraph of Chapter 33. He is letting the reader know that capitalist private prosperity can only exist once the private property of the individual producer has been expropriated and annihilated.


Problems of Non-Covid Patients and Health Care Services during Pandemic Period: A Micro level Study with reference to Chennai City, Tamilnadu

  https://www.eurchembull.com/uploads/paper/92a2223312e11453a5559262c1cd4542.pdf ABSTRACT Background: COVID-19 has disrupted India's eco...